Riemann for Anti-Dummies: Part 44 : Principles and Powers

Riemann for Anti-Dummies Part 44

PRINCIPLES AND POWERS

Rembrandt van Rijn’s masterpiece, ?Aristotle Contemplating a Bust of Homer?, conveys a principle that leads directly into the deeper implications of Gauss’ and Riemann’s complex domain. In the painting, the eyes of both figures are fixed directly before them, yet, Aristotle’s gaze is insufficient to guide him. To find his way, he reaches forward to touch the likeness of the poet, who, though blind in life, leads the blocked philosopher in a direction he would otherwise be incapable of finding.

Like the navigators of ancient maritime civilizations, Rembrandt’s Homer knows that straight-ahead is not necessarily where your eyes point. When following a course across some wide expanse, these discoverers would mark their passage by noting the motions of celestial bodies, the which were charted as changes of positions on the inside of the sphere whose center was the eyes of the observer. When the observer’s position changed, so did the positions of everything on the sphere, but the manifold of vision remained a sphere and the eyes of the observer remained at its center. A stationary observer would note certain changes in the positions of celestial bodies over the course of a night and from night to night. An observer moving on the Earth noted these changes, plus the changes in these changes resulting from his own motion. These changes, and changes of changes, formed a map in the mind of the explorer — not a static map, but a map of the principles that caused the map to change. It is the map of principles on which all explorers, from those days to this, place their trust.

While a map, such as one of positions of celestial bodies on the inside of a sphere, can be represented directly to our senses, a map of principles can only be represented by the methods exemplified by Rembrandt’s painting. Principles do not appear as objects in the picture, but as ironies that evoke the formation of their corresponding ideas in the imagination of the viewer. The scientist in pursuit of unknown principles, must master the art of recognizing the ironies that appear, not only from known principles, but those still to be discovered; the latter emerging as paradoxes. In the case of physical principles investigated by mathematical images, these paradoxes present themselves as anomalies, as for example, the emergence of “-1, within the domain of algebraic equations. The poetic scientist takes the existence of such anomalies as evidence of a principle yet to be discovered, and re-thinks how his map must change to include this new principle. C.F. Gauss measured this type of transformation as a change in curvature. This work was extended by B. Riemann through his theory of complex functions, most notably in his major works on the hypergeometric and abelian functions.

What has failed Rembrandt’s Aristotle, is not his eyes, but his map. A map which has changed by a principle, that on principle, he insists doesn’t exist and cannot be known if it did. Disoriented he’s left to grope in the only direction he knows straight ahead. Fortunately for him, straight ahead stands the lifeless image of Homer, possessed with the power to light his way.

Curvature and Power

This method of discovery is already evident in the work of Archytas, who taught that the physics of the universe could be discovered through investigations of the paradoxes arising in arithmetic, geometry, spheric (astronomy) and music. His collaborator, Plato, prescribed mastery of these four branches of one science, as essential for the development of political leadership.

The solution Archytas provided for doubling the cube exemplifies the principle. As it was developed more fully in previous pedagogical discussions (see Riemann for Anti-Dummies Part 42) the problems of doubling the line, square and cube, presents us with the existence of magnitudes of successively higher powers, each of which is associated with a distinct principle. The Pythagoreans called the power that doubles the line, arithmetic, and the power that doubles the square geometric, which they associated with musical intervals as well as mathematical ones. In their most general form, the arithmetic is associated with a division of a line, while the geometric is associated with a division of a circle. (See figure 1 and figure 2). From Gauss’ standpoint, the change in power from the arithmetic to geometric is associated with a change in curvature from rectilinear to circular.

Figure 1

Figure 2

As Hippocrates of Cios indicated, to double the cube requires placing two geometric means between two extremes. At first blush, this can be accomplished within the domain of circular action by connecting two circles to each other. (See figure 3.) Thus, while the difference between the arithmetic and geometric presents clearly a change in curvature, the power associated with generating two geometric means, in first approximation, seems to require only another circle, hence, no change in curvature.

Figure 3

Yet, when the specific physical problem of doubling the cube is posed, that is, to find two geometric means between two determined extremes, (in this case 1 and 2) the existence of the higher power emerges into the map, as a new type of curvature. (See animation 1.) As can be seen in the diagram, to find two geometric means between 1 and 2, we must find the place along the circumference of the circle for point P so that the line OB is one-half of OA. This will occur somewhere along the pathway traveled by B as P moves around the circle from O to A. But, as the dotted line which traces that path indicates, this curve is not a circular arc, and is, in fact, non-uniform with respect to the circle. Thus, the existence of the yet to be discovered principle, emerges through the presence of an anomalous change in curvature in our map.

Animation 1

This anomaly takes on an entirely different characteristic in Archytas’ construction using the torus, cylinder and cone. (See figure 4 andanimation 2.) When the torus and cylinder are generated by rotating one circle orthogonally around another, the motion of point P is now simultaneously on two different curves: the circle and the curve formed by the intersection of the torus and the cylinder. An observer facing the rotating circle, and who was rotating at exactly the same speed as the circle, would only see point P move around the circumference of the circle and would adequately conclude that one geometric mean between two extremes is a function of circular action alone. But, as indicated above, the emergence of the non-circular curvature of the path of point B, would indicate to such an observer, the existence of a new principle causing the motion of P around the circle. Archytas’ construction takes that new principle into account, by determining the motion of P around the circle as a function of P’s motion along the curve formed by the intersection of the torus and cylinder. In other words, the circular rotation of P is only a shadow of a higher form of curvature. That latter curve expresses both the power to produce one geometric mean between two extremes, and also, when combined with a cone, to produce two. (See figure 4.)

Figure 4

Animation 2

Two other examples, presented summarily, will help illustrate the point. Kepler, like all astronomers before and since, observed the motions of the planets as circular arcs on the inside of a sphere. His discovery of the elliptical nature of these orbits occurred, not by suddenly seeing an ellipse, but by his recognition that the 8′ of an arc deviation between the circular image of the planet’s orbit on the celestial sphere, and the circular image of the Earth’s motion (as reflected in the motion of the fixed stars on that same celestial sphere), was evidence of a new principle of planetary motion. The new principle manifested itself as a change in curvature within his map of principles. He measured that change in curvature by measuring equal areas instead of equal arcs, and measuring eccentricities by the proportions that correspond to musical harmonics.

Similarly, Leibniz and Bernoulli determined that the catenary was not the parabola that Gallileo wrongly considered it to be, by showing that the slight deviation of the curvature of the physical hanging chain, from the curvature of the parabola, was evidence that the chain was being governed by a different principle than the one Gallileo assumed. Gallileo demanded, as if in a bi-polar rage, that the chain conform to a parabolic shape, because he was obsessed with his mathematical formula that the velocity of a falling body varies according to the square root of distance fallen. Leibniz and Bernoulli, demonstrated that the chain was, in truth, obeying a higher principle, the non-algebraic, transcendental principle associated with Leibniz’ discovery of natural logarithms. A principle that the enraged Gallileo was incapable of conceiving.

Gaussian Curvature

To proceed further it is important to distinguish between commonplace sense-certainty notions of curvature and the rigorous understanding of that idea associated with Gauss. The commonplace notion, associated with the doctrines of Gallileo, Newton, Euler, et al. is that curvature is a deviation from the straight. But, from the standpoint of the planet, for example, ?straight?, is a unique elliptical path; or, from the standpoint of a link in a chain, ?straight? is the catenary curve. It is only a self-deluded fool who thinks that ?straight? can be determined by some arbitrary, abstract dictate. Rather, ?straight? is a function of the set of principles that are determining the action. The addition of a new principle will change the direction of ?straight?. That change in principle is measured as a change in curvature.

This is the basis from which Gauss developed his, ?General Investigations of Curved Surfaces?. He considered a curved surface to be a set of invariable principles that determined the nature of action on that surface. As long as that set of principles was not changed, the nature of the action did not change, even if the surface was bent or stretched. The nature of the action could only be changed, by a change in the set of principles that defined the surface. Gauss measured such a change in principle as a change in curvature, which in turn, determined what is ?straight? with respect to that set of principles.

Furthermore, Gauss showed, as Leibniz did for curves, that this set of invariable principles were expressed in the smallest elements of the surface. Consequently, from the smallest pieces of ?straight? curves (geodesics) on the surface, and their directions, the curvature of the surface could be determined. (This aspect of Gauss’ work will be developed in a future pedagogical.)

The method Gauss developed to measure curvature had its roots in Kepler’s method for measuring the elliptical nature of a planetary orbit, the which was generalized by Leibniz into his development of the calculus. Confronting the difficulty of measuring the planet’s non-uniform elliptical motion directly, Kepler mapped the constantly changing speed and direction of the planet onto a circular path, and measured the planet’s action by the relationships among the three anomalies (eccentric, mean and true) that appeared in the circular map. (See Summer 1998 Fidelio pp. 29-34).

To measure the curvature of a surface, Gauss extended Kepler’s method from the mapping of a curve onto a circle, to the mapping of a surface onto a sphere, a method he likened to the ancient use of the celestial sphere in astronomy. In that case, the motion of celestial bodies are mapped by the changing directions of lines from the observer to the body’s image on the inside of the celestial sphere. Since whatever principle is governing the body’s motion, is governing the changes in direction of those lines, measuring the map of those changes in direction is an indirect measurement of the governing principle.

Gauss recognized that the invariable principles governing a surface could be expressed by the changing direction of the lines perpendicular to the surface at every point, called ?normals?. While at any point of a surface there are an infinite number of tangents (See Figure 4) there is a unique tangent plane for each point, which in turn defines a unique normal that is perpendicular direction to this tangent plane. The direction of the normal is a function of the curvature of the surface. (This is a principle of physical geometry, as exemplified by the determination of the physical horizon as that direction that is perpendicular to the pull of gravity.)

The sphere has the unique characteristic that all its normals are also radial lines. Using this property, every normal to a surface will correspond to a radial line of a sphere that is pointing in the same direction. As a normal moves around on a surface, its direction changes. If a radial line of the sphere is made to change its direction in the same way as the normal to the surface, it will trace out a curve on the surface of the sphere, that will reflect the principle governing the changes in direction of the normal on the surface.

This is illustrated by example in animation 3 and animation 4. In these examples, the part of the ellipsoid marked out by the yellow curve, is mapped onto a sphere. As the red stick moves around the ellipsoid, its changing direction is determined by the changing curvature of the surface. These changes are mapped onto a sphere, by the motion of the blue stick, which emanates from the center of the sphere and is always pointing in the same direction as the red stick. Gauss called the area marked out by the blue stick on the sphere the, ?total or integral curvature? of the surface. If the red stick were moving along a plane, its direction would not change, and the blue stick would not move. Since this would obviously mark out no area, Gauss defined a plane as a surface of zero curvature. The greater the area marked out on the sphere, the greater the curvature of the surface being mapped.

Animation 3

Animation 4

This can be seen from the above two examples. In animation 3 the red stick is moving around a large area of the ellipsoid, but because that region is less curved, its direction doesn’t change very much, and the corresponding area on the sphere is small. Whereas, in animation 4, the area on the ellipsoid is small, but very curved, so the area marked out on the sphere is larger.

This total curvature does not change even if the surface is deformed. For example, try and determine the spherical map of a part of a cone or a cylinder.

Using this method, Gauss was able to not only measure the ?amount? of curvature, but he was also able to distinguish types of curvature that are determined by different sets of principles. For example, animation 5 illustrates the mapping of a surface called a ?monkey saddle?. (This type of surface should be familiar to those who have been working on Gauss’ 1799 proof of the fundamental theorem of algebra.) In this mapping the curvature of the area denoted by the yellow curve on the monkey saddle is mapped to the sphere. As the red stick moves once around the area on the monkey saddle, the blue stick marks out the spherical area twice. This double covering of the spherical area indicates that the curvature of the monkey saddle embodies a different set of principles than the curvature of the ellipsoid.

Animation 5

A still different type of curvature emerges when Gauss’ mapping is applied to a torus as in animation 6, and animation 7. In animation 6, a part of the outside of the torus is mapped producing a corresponding area on the sphere, similar to what happened on the ellipsoid. But, in animation 7, the area of the torus is situated on both the inner and outer part. The mapping of these directions produces a figure eight type of curve on the sphere that crosses itself at the north pole. Each time the red stick crosses the circle that forms the boundary between the inner and outer part of the torus, the blue stick crosses the north pole of the sphere, with one loop of the figure eight corresponding to the inner part of torus, and the other loop the outer part. The area on the torus is bounded by a non-intersecting curve, while its map on the sphere is bounded by an intersecting one. The presence of this singularity on the spherical map indicates that the boundary between the inner and outer parts of the torus is a transition from one type of curvature to another. Consequently, the torus must be governed by a different set of principles than the ellipsoid or monkey saddle a set of principles that encompass a transition between two different types of curvature.

Animation 6

Animation 7

To summarize: for the ellipsoid, the Gaussian mapping produced a simple area whose size varied with the curvature of the surface. The mapping of the monkey saddle produced an area that was double covered. The mapping of the torus, produced a singularity. These mappings not only measure the ?amount? of total curvature of the part of the surface mapped, but the appearance of anomalies and singularities in the mapping, indicate the presence of additional principles of curvature as well.

Like the Chorus in Shakespeare’s Henry V, who, alone on an empty stage, summons the imagination of the audience to envision the real principles of history and statecraft that are to be depicted, these anomalies and singularities call the attention of the scientist to imagine the set of principles that produced them. Therein, is where

Riemann for Anti-Dummies: Part 43 : Isaac Newton: Godmother of Baby Boomer Bookkeeping

Riemann for Anti-Dummies Part 43

ISAAC NEWTON: GODMOTHER OF BABY-BOOMER BOOKKEEPING

Baby Boomers, wishing to cure themselves of the afflictions endemic to their generation, will find the administration of a purgative that clears their spirit of the prejudices expressed by Newton’s first “law” of motion, to be of great therapeutic benefit. This “law”, which Newton cribbed from Paolo Sarpi’s Galileo, asserts that bodies in motion move uniformly in straight lines, and bodies at rest stay at rest, unless disturbed. The spread of the epistemological disease associated with this edict has been greatly facilitated by the high priests of modern science, who, acting in the manner and style of their Babylonian and Roman predecessors, have promulgated it as a “law of nature”. The contagion has now permeated into such diverse areas of human activity as the design and operation of space vehicles, the maintenance of basic economic infrastructure, the tragic choice of political candidates, and the truthful keeping of financial books.

The latter is, perhaps, one of the most effective clinical methods for recognizing the extent of the underlying malady, for Newton’s “first law” is exemplary of the bookkeeping methods typical of Enron, WorldCom, Winstar and other Baby Boomer parodies of Shelley’s Ozymandias. Today’s “aggressive accounting” is, in fact, a subset of Newton’s effort to foist a false set of books on the entire universe, and account for all real physical action as an aberration caused by the mysterious intervention of “outside forces”. Just as Baby Boomers do today, Newton absolved himself of moral responsibility with the sophistic disclaimer, “Hypothesis non fingo”, which is otherwise more truthfully stated as, “the Devil made me do it.”

As Bernhard Riemann noted in an unpublished philosophical fragment:

“The distinction that Newton makes between laws of motion, or axioms, and hypotheses, does not seem tenable to me. The law of inertia is the hypothesis: If a material point were present alone in the world and moved in space with a definite velocity, then it would constantly maintain this velocity.”

Newton’s extrication of hypothesis from the universe, like the keeping of a Baby Boomer’s “feel good” set of financial books, is nothing but self-delusion. As Kepler demonstrated, following in the intellectual tradition of Plato and Cusa, the trajectories of all material bodies, such as planets, are determined by a set of physical principles, which are to the physical universe as hypotheses are to the human mind. But, while non-living material bodies, act according to the principle of mind, human beings possess one, giving them the capacity (power), whether they wish to acknowledge it or not, to control and change their trajectories by changing the principles that govern them. Given this, the willful creation of hypotheses, like a truthful set of books, is the only sane course for humans to chart.

What is Straight Anyway?

To chart this course we must recognize, as Riemann, his teacher Gauss and his teacher Kaestner did, that Newton was pulling the classic magician’s trick with his first law of motion. By directing the attention of the observer to a mythical material point, the credulous audience focuses their attention on what appears to be the straight-line path of the point. While fixated on what they imagine they see, the audience fails to account for the unstated, but controlling, assumption governing the action, to wit: the material point is moving in a plane as defined in Euclid’s Elements. In other words, the straight-line path of the material point is a function of the assumption that the space in which it moves is a flat plane. In this way, the books are rigged to produce the pre-desired result.

Gauss caught on to this trick in his teenage years. He recognized that the characteristics of the plane could not be established, as Euclid did, by a definition. Writing in his notebook on July 28, 1797, “I have demonstrated the possibility of the plane”.

Thirty-five years later he elaborated this note to his former classmate Wolfgang Bolyai:

“In order to treat geometry properly from the beginning, it is essential to prove the possibility of the plane (Planum); the usual definition contains too much and already implies an intrinsic hidden theorem. One must be amazed that every writer from Euclid until the most recent times have been so careless: but this difficulty is of an entirely different nature than the difficulty of determining Sigma from S (left from right-bmd)…

“The impossibility of determining, a priori, between Sigma and S is the clearest proof that Kant was wrong to claim that space was only the form of our perception (Anshauung). I have indicated the basis for this in a little essay…which contains the quintessence of my view on imaginary numbers in a few pages.”

What Gauss was pointing to is that Euclid’s definition of a plane contains the assumption that the straight-lines in it will behave in certain ways. Gauss rejected this approach. Instead, he understood a plane to be that surface in which straight-lines obeyed certain provable relationships, specifically, those relationships that flow from rotational action. Rotational action does not {define} a plane. Rather, the plane is that surface in which the rotational action which occurs, produces certain relationships among straight-lines.

From the standpoint of our earlier examination of Newton’s first law, the straight-line uniform motion of the lonely material point occurs because it is assumed it is taking place in a flat plane. Newton, like all magicians, didn’t want anyone in his credulous audience to ask, “Is the universe actually flat?”, or even more fundamentally, “Is it possible for anything to be flat?”

That is the type of question that anyone wishing for civilization to survive, should begin asking.

Riemann for Anti-Dummies: Part 42 : Archytus from the Standpoint of Cusa, Gauss, and Riemann

Riemann for Anti-Dummies Part 42

ARCHYTAS FROM THE STANDPOINT OF CUSA, GAUSS, AND RIEMANN

A citizen in 2003 A.D., wishing to muster the conceptual power necessary to comprehend today’s historical, political and economic crisis, and to act to change it, will find it of great benefit to bind into one thought, Archytas’ construction for finding two mean proportionals between two extremes, (circa 400 B.C.), with Bernhard Riemann’s 1854 lecture, “On the Hypothesis which Underlie the Foundations of Geometry”. Two thoughts, separated temporally by 2400 years, recreated simultaneously by one mind yours.

The summary of the relevant concept, spoken by the then 28 year old Riemann acting under the tutelage of the 77 year old C.F. Gauss, focuses on the relationship of the idea to that which creates it:

“Accordingly, I have proposed to myself at first the problem of constructing the concept of a multiply extended magnitude out of general notions of quantity. From this it will result that a multiply extended magnitude is susceptible of various metric relations and that space accordingly constitutes only a particular case of a triply-extended magnitude. A necessary sequel of this is that the propositions of geometry are not derivable from general concepts of quantity, but that those properties by which space is distinguished from other conceivable triply extended magnitudes can be gathered only from experience. There arises from this the problem of searching out the simplest facts by which the metric relations of space can be determined, a problem which in nature of things is not quite definite; for several systems of simple facts can be stated which would suffice for determining the metric relations of space; the most important for present purposes is that laid down for foundations by Euclid. These facts are, like all facts, not necessary but of a merely empirical certainty; they are hypotheses; one may therefore inquire into their probability, which is truly very great within the bounds of observation, and thereafter decide concerning the admissibility of protracting them outside the limits of observation, not only toward the immeasurably large, but also toward the immeasurably small.”

It must be kept in mind, that Archytas, like Riemann and Gauss, was anti-Euclidean. In fact, even Euclid was more anti-Euclidean than today’s neo-Aristotelean followers of Galileo, Newton and Kant, who assert that physical space-time conforms, a-priori, to the axioms, postulates and definitions of Euclidean geometry. No where in Euclid’s Elements is such a preposterous assertion stated. Rather, the Elements are a compilation of earlier discoveries that could never have been produced by the logical deductive methods used in the Elements. The actual method of discovery is best indicated when the Elements are read backwards; from the 13th book on the spherical derivation of the five regular solids, to the 10th book on incommensurables, to the middle books on proportions, to the opening sections on the circular derivation of constructions in a plane.

Archytas’ magnificent composition could only have been produced by a mind closer to Riemann’s than Euclid’s, and, having lived and worked nearly a century earlier, we can be assured that his was not constricted by the deductive method of the Elements, let alone its later Aristotelean transmogrifications. The few extant fragments of Archytas indicate his concept of mathematics was far different from today’s formalists:

“Mathematicians seem to me to have excellent discernment, and it is not at all strange that they should think correctly about the particulars that are; for inasmuch as they can discern excellently about the physics of the universe, they are also likely to have excellent perspective on the particulars that are. Indeed, they have transmitted to us a keen discernment about the velocities of the stars and their risings and settings, and about geometry, arithmetic, astronomy, and, not least of all, music. These seem to be sister sciences, for they concern themselves with the first two related forms of being number and magnitude.”

As with his collaborator Plato, Archytas understood that the betterment of humanity depended on the improvement of the cognitive powers of the mind through pedagogical exercises:

“When mathematical reasoning has been found, it checks political faction and increases concord, for there is no unfair advantage in its presence, and equality reigns. With mathematical reasoning we smooth out differences in our dealings with each other. Through it the poor take from the powerful, and the rich give to the needy, both trusting in it to obtain an equal share.”

However, today’s responsible citizen need not rely merely on fragmentary quotes to bring Archytas’ method into his or her mind. A more secure approach is directly accessible–coming to know for oneself, Archytas’ solution for the problem of doubling the cube a method advocated by Archytas himself:

“To become knowledgeable about things one does not know, one must either learn from others or find out for oneself. Now learning derives from someone else and is foreign, whereas finding out is of and by oneself. Finding out without seeking is difficult and rare, but with seeking it is manageable and easy, though someone who does not know how to seek cannot find.”

The Polyphonic Determination of Mean Proportionals

To begin to obtain knowledge of Archytas’ method, one must throw out all axiomatic/deductive approaches and adopt the physical/geometrical approach demonstrated by Jonathan Tennenbaum in his quite notable pedagogical exercise: “A Note: Why Modern Mathematicians Can’t Understand Archytas” That discussion should be throughly worked through and forms an excellent basis for the pedagogical workshops now taking place among youth organizers and others. That argument is summarized here with the aid of some graphics and animations.

To double the cube, Archytas focused on the more general form of the problem posed by Hippocrates of Cios, that of placing two means between two extremes. Hippocrates had recognized that when doubling the square, the areas of the squares produced, as well as the corresponding sides, were all in what the Pythagoreans called “geometric” proportion. A similar relationship held when doubling cubes, but with one notable exception. Instead of one geometric mean between each action, the cube required two.

For example, if we take a square and double its side, the area of the square so produced quadruples. Thus, the square whose area is double, is the geometric mean between the original square and the square produced by doubling its side. That proportion expressed in numbers is 1:2::2:4. This same proportion is reflected among the sides of the three squares. That is, the side of the square of 1 is to the side of the square of two, as the side of the square of two is to the side of the square of four. Or, in numbers, 1:\/2::\/2:2. Thus, doubling a square amounts to constructing the geometric mean between 1 and 2.

However, when the edge of a cube is doubled, the volume of the cube increases from 1 to 8. From the standpoint of whole numbers, there are two geometric means between 1 and 8, specifically 2 and 4. Hippocrates noted that a similar proportionality exists between the edges of these cubes. The problem, as Riemann would recognize it, is extending this relationship outside the realm of visible observation between 1 and 8, into the smaller interval between 1 and 2. The discrepancy between what can be done in the large and with what can be done in the small, is analogous to the idea of a changing geodesic from the macro-physical to the micro-physical domain, and indicates that the doubling of cube is an action of a higher power, as Plato defines power.

The relationship between the problem of doubling the cube and the problem of finding two geometric means between two extremes, can prove a stubborn one to master for those stuck in logical/deductive habits. The root of this mental block is in large part due to the false, but persistent, habit of trying to understand things from the bottom up. While in the domain of squares, the geometric means from one to eight are created one at a time, one, then two, then four, then eight; in the domain of cubes, these two geometric means, must be created all at once from the top down.

Archytas, who understood music, geometry, number and sphaerics (astronomy) as one, would have no more problem with this than J.S. Bach, Mozart, Beethoven, Schubert, Schumann or Brahms. For the well-tempered system of bel-canto polyphony is not produced from the bottom up, note by note. Rather, each note is determined from the relationships that arise from bel-canto sung polyphony. Thus, think of the placing of two means between two extremes in the same epistemological light as a musical composition. The composer’s idea of the composition determines the relationship among the notes. The question Archytas solved, was, “What composition produces two geometric means between two extremes?”

As demonstrated in the above cited pedagogical discussion by Jonathan Tennenbaum, the placing of one geometric mean is a function of circular rotation, not the generation of squares. While the doubling of the square requires finding the geometric mean between 1 and 2, the circle expresses the placement of a geometric mean between any two extremes. (See figure 1.) In the figure, triangle OPA is inscribed in a semi-circle making the angle at P a right angle.(fn.1.) A line drawn from P perpendicular to diameter at Q, forms a whole set of geometric proportions. The one that most concerns us here is OQ:OP::OP::OA. As P rotates around the circle from A to O, OP remains the geometric mean between OQ and OA, even though the proportion between OQ and OA changes from 1:1 to 1:0.(fn2.) (See animation 1.)

Figure 1

Animation 1

As indicated in Jonathan’s pedagogical, a second set of geometric proportions can be linked to this first set, by drawing a circle around right angle OPQ and finding B as a projection of Q onto OP. (See figure 2.) This produces the double set of geometric proportions OB:OQ::OQ:OP::OP::OA. Now, as P moves from A to O, not only do the geometric relationships between OQ, OP and OA change, but so do the geometric relationships between OQ, OB and OP. (See animation 2.)

Figure 2

Animation 2

Think of these sets of relationships polyphonically. OQ:OP::OP:OA is one voice. OB:OQ::OQ::OP is a second voice. The internal relationships within each voice are the same, but together they form a relationship between two sets of relationships, akin to the voices in a two part fugue.

The problem Archytas confronted is expressed by the non-uniform nature of the curve traced by B as P moves around the larger circle. In order to double the cube, there must be some definite way to determine a ratio between OB and OA of 1:2.

Archytas recognized that this could not be determined in what Riemann called a doubly-extended manifold, but rather, was derived from the higher powers associated with a triply-extended manifold.

Archytas effected this by generating the first set of geometric means from rotating one circle (with diameter AO) perpendicular to another (with diameter OD). (See animation 3.) A point P on circle AO connected perpendicularly to a point Q on the circumference of circle OD, produces the geometric relationship, OQ:OP::OP::OA. The action of the rotating circle AO produces a torus. (See animation 4.)

Animation 3

Animation 4

The rotation of PQ produces a cylinder (See animation 5.) The intersection of the torus and cylinder forms a curve of double curvature, which expresses, from the standpoint of a higher power, the geometric relationships between OQ, OP and OA. Now, when Q is projected to a point B on OP the relationship OB:OQ::OQ:OP::OP:OA is produced. (See Figure 3.)

Animation 5

Figure 3

From this, the magnitude that doubles the cube can be found by constructing OM as a chord of circle OQD so that it is of diameter OD. (See Figure 4.) Rotate chord OM around the axis OD until it coincides with line OP. This action produces a cone with apex at O and axis OD. P now lies at the intersection of a cone, torus and cylinder. After this rotation, M will coincide with B and the length of OB will equal OM. Consequently, if OB=1, OQ is the edge of the cube whose volume is 2; OP is the edge of the cube whose volume is 4; and OA is the edge of the cube whose volume is 8.

Figure 4

The Maximum and Minimum

With the just completed work fresh in mind, step back and ask an elementary question. What universal principle is expressed by the physical characteristic that a doubly extended manifold expresses one geometric mean between two extremes, while a triply extended one requires two? As Plato states in the Timaeus, this is not an abstract question, but one necessary to know in order to understand the real world:

“Now if the body of the One had to come into existence as a plane surface, having no depth, one mean would have sufficed to bind together both itself and its fellow terms; but now it is otherwise; for it behoved it to be solid of shape and what brings solids into unison is never one mean but always two.”

A crucial insight can be gained when this question is examined from the standpoint of Nicholas of Cusa’s principle of the Maximum and Minimum.

Look back at our initial exploration of geometric means. We discovered that this relationship is expressed by a right angle in a circle. But, there was an underlying assumption that we didn’t investigate. What is a right angle? Should we accept some definition, such as Euclid’s, that a right angle is that angle formed when two lines that intersect form two angles that are equal? Should we accept the definition of right angle as that angle inscribed in a semi-circle, when such a definition assumes that the sum of the angles of a triangle equals two right angles? As Kaestner and Gauss would later demonstrate, such definitions already assume that the manifold in which the action occurs is characterized by infinite flatness.

Even before Kaestner and Gauss raised these questions, Cusa recognized that such formal definitions never lead to the truth. For Cusa, the truth is the unqualifiedly Maximum, which, in the Absolute, coincides with the unqualifiedly Minimum.

“Therefore, the truth, which is itself the measure of things, is not comprehensible except through itself. And one sees that in the coincidence of the measure and the measured. Indeed, in everything this side of the infinite, the measure and the measured differ according to more or less. In God, however, they coincide. The coincidence of opposites is therefore like the periphery of the infinite circle. The distance of opposites is as the periphery of the finite polygon. Therefore, in theological figures the complement of that which can be known is to know this, namely, that in the infinite the difference of the measure and the measured is in God equality or coincidence. Hence, the measuring is there infinite rectitude. And the infinite circular line is measurable through infinite rectitude. And the measuring itself is the unity or the connection of both.”

This method of the maximum and minimum is already implicit in the problem addressed by Archytas. The maximum and minimum coincide in God, but “this side of the infinite” they’re opposites. Physical action, can be thought of as least-action, or a mean between the extremes of the minimum and maximum.

As Cusa notes, the circle is generated as the action that encompasses the maximum area by the minimum circumference, otherwise known as “isoperimetric”. This action of circular rotation, itself contains a maximum and minimum. If the rotation begins from a point A, then there is some point O at which the rotating point has reached a maximum divergence from A and begins to converge back towards A. Thus, the circle, which is itself a maximum/minimum, contains within it, another maximum/minimum, expressed by the ends of the diameter as points of maximum divergence.

This principle of maximum divergence within a circle, also contains within it, a maximum and minimum. The angle formed by a line pivoting about the center of the circle reaches an angle of maximum divergence, which now defines a right angle, which Cusa calls the maximum acute angle and the minimum obtuse angle. In other words, instead of defining a right angle as a thing, think of it as a maximum/minimum within a circle, which is itself a maximum/minimum within a doubly-extended manifold. It is here, in the nature of the doubly- extended manifold, that the minimum/maximum characteristics expressed by the circle, and in turn, the right angle, are determined.

Thought of from this standpoint, the geometric mean expresses this maximum/minimum relationship of what Riemann would call a doubly-extended manifold. In sum, the circle expresses the maximum/minimum characteristic of a doubly-extended manifold; the right angle, in turn, expresses the maximum/minimum characteristic of a circle. From Cusa’s standpoint, the geometric mean can be thought of as the mean between the maximum and minimum right angle, (as illustrated in the in the first animation.)

Thought of in this way, the geometric mean is not produced by squares. Rather, the squares are artifacts, generated by the placing of one geometric mean between two extremes, which is the characteristic least action principle of a doubly-extended manifold of zero-curvature.

Now on to the real world of solids as exemplified by cubes. Cubes express two geometric means between two extremes. From the standpoint of Cusa’s maximum/minimum, this relationship must express a mean between the minimum and maximum in what Riemann would call a triply-extended manifold. The expression of the maximum/minimum in a triply- extended manifold is spherical action, which encloses the maximum volume in the minimum surface, and produces two orthogonal degrees of circular action. Each circle expresses a complete set of geometric means. But, the two means that produce solid bodies, such as cubes, are only generated when the spherical action is “unfolded” as in Archytas’ construction.

As in the case of the square, the cube does not produce two means between two extremes. Cubes are artifacts generated when two geometric means are placed between two extremes of spherical action, when that action is “unfolded” as in Archytas’ composition. This is a characteristic least-action principle of a triply-extended manifold.

Figure 4

Kepler’s Orbits and the Catenary

Cusa’s method of maximum/minimum led to a revolution in scientific thinking as typified by Kepler’s determination of the harmonic ordering of planetary motion. The position of any planet within its orbit, Kepler demonstrated, is determined by the minimum and maximum speeds of that orbit. From aphelion the planet increases its speed non-uniformly as determined by the speed it intends to be at when it reaches perihelion, and inversely, from perihelion back to aphelion. Thus, each planet’s orbit is a type of mean between these two extremes. Kepler further showed that these intra-orbital extremes when thought of together, form a set of means, as expressed by the musical harmonic relationships among them.

Similarly for Leibniz’ principle of the catenary. As both he and Bernoulli showed, the catenary unfolds its “orbital” pathway from its lowest point, which is the only point that holds up no chain. From a physical standpoint, the catenary is a mean, a least-action pathway, between the maximum potential force and minimum potential force, which are exerted at right angles to each other. This example will rankle anyone stuck in a Cartesian coordinate system, where the horizontal and vertical axes are straight-lines, and the mean between them is just another straight-line at a 45 degree angle to both. In Leibniz’ physical geometry, the vertical and horizontal are the potential maximum and minimum of physical action, and the catenary is the least action pathway between these two extremes.

Freed, now, from the “ivory tower” notions of Euclidean geometry, as Archytas was, we can gain a greater comprehension of the expression of Cusa’s principle of the maximum/minimum in the Gauss/Riemann complex domain. This is where we’ll begin in the next installment.

FOOTNOTES

1. This should not be taken for granted, and so the reader is encouraged to discover a demonstration that an angle inscribed in a semi-circle is a right angle. The original proof of this is attributed to Thales. The proof in Euclid, III. 31, is based on Euclid’s earlier proof that the sum of the angles of a triangle is equal to two right angles, which Kaestner, Gauss and Riemann would later note depends on the parallel postulate, which in turn depends on an assumption about the nature of the curvature of space. As, Riemann noted in his 1854 habilitation lecture, “these facts are, like all facts, not necessary but of a merely empirical certainty; they are hypotheses;”

2. Here we confront another paradox of abstract mathematics between the expression of the geometric mean in numerical terms, and its physical geometric expression.

Riemann for Anti-Dummies: Part 41 : The Long Life of the Catenary

Riemann for Anti-Dummies Part 41

DIE WIDMUNG

The following pedagogy is dedicated to the celebration of Lyn and Helga’s silver wedding anniversary on Dec. 29, which is an occasion for joy, not only for said happy couple, but for all people around the world to whom this marriage has contributed such happiness over the past quarter-century.

The Long Life of the Catenary: From Brunelleschi to LaRouche

The shift from a consumer society to a producer one is, fundamentally, a question of understanding power. For consumers, the world is a universe of magical powers, from which the apparent requirements of life are obtained through the intercession of high priests. Such people, when confronted with a turn of events, such as the present, in which the powers on which they’ve relied no longer deliver, become frightened. They demand action from their increasingly impotent priesthood, who, despite all boasts to the contrary, fail to produce results. They then take matters into their own hands, adopting ever increasing desperate rituals designed to appeal directly to the powers on which their hopes are pinned. The high priests, seeking to restore “consumer confidence” and regain their positions of lofty authority, suggest to the frightened populace, that new rituals be performed and new incantations be recited. Each desperate effort fails to bring about any respite from the crisis. Suspicions mount that the unseen potencies have either gone deaf or departed the scene. Dead or deaf, the thought that such powers might never have existed is their ultimate terror. Even if these forces are now believed gone, the idea of their previous existence not only persists, but continues to govern the thoughts and actions of the populari, feeding the hopeless pessimism that leads such unfortunate creatures into a contorted dance reminiscent of those depicted in a Breugel masterpiece.

There was a similar state of affairs in 14th century Florence, when in the aftermath of the Black Death in which nearly 80% of the Florentine population perished, a group of artists succeeded in launching the project to build a Dome with a diameter of 42 meters over the church of Santa Maria del Fiore. (See Figure 1.)

Figure 1

When the decision to undertake that project was made in 1367, the man who would ultimately execute it, Filippo Brunelleshci, was not even born, but the intention that would guide him was already embedded in the proposed size of the structure, and the requirements of its design. The Dome was to be equal in size to the Roman Pantheon, that temple to the mystical powers on whose behalf Roman popular opinion ruled. (See Figure 2a and Figure 2b.)

Figure 2a

Figure 2b

From the time of its construction in 128 A.D. under Emperor Hadrian, the Pantheon had remained the largest domed structure in the world. But, unlike the Pantheon, the Florentine Dome was to be beautiful from both the inside and out. It was to be a complete break with the pantheonic culture that, even though the Emperors had long since ceased to rule directly under its name, had continued to persist for more than 13 centuries and had brought about the very recent calamity from which Europe was still reeling.

The Dome was a project of bold optimism. It would not only span such a large structure, but by being self-supporting and free standing, it would demonstrate a principle that would transform the entire surrounding region, and through the minds of travelers and the imaginations of those with whom they would speak, the entire world.

The full implications of the principles necessary to construct the Dome were not known to the Dome’s original designers, but, to accomplish the feat, Brunelleschi would have to discover, apply, and communicate a form of the universal principle of least-action whose further elaboration would unfold over the ensuing 500 years. The crucial development occurred in 1988, when Lyndon LaRouche, faced with imminent unjust imprisonment, visited the Dome and recognized the implications of Brunelleschi’s discoveries for the subsequent breakthroughs of Leibniz, Gauss and Riemann, and for the future, development of a new physical science.(See 1989 issue of 21st Century with Dome on the cover.)

The Dome and Anti-Euclidean Geometry

Imagine yourself in 1420 looking at the octagonal drum of Santa Maria del Fiore without the Dome. What do you see? Empty space? If so, you would never envision, let alone build, the Dome. The construction of the Dome required a mastery of principles not visible to the eye. Not the invisible mystical powers of the Pantheon, but the universal physical principles, which, though unseen, are known clearly through the imagination. For the scientist, like the artist, there is no empty space, no empty canvass, no blank slate. There is a manifold of physical principles characterized by a set of relationships whose expression takes the ultimate form of the work of art. To visualize the unbuilt Dome, as the artist Brunelleschi would, imagine the physical principles, and the bricks and mortar take the required form.

This is the basis on which to begin to construct a physical geometry from the standpoint of Brunelleschi, Leibniz, Gauss, Riemann and LaRouche.

To grasp this, think of the difference between abstract geometrical shapes, and the physical geometry of bricks and mortar.

Start with a vertical column. An abstract geometrical line, according to Euclid, is that extension in empty space which has only length. No matter how long the line, its width, is always the same, namely, nil. However, when building a vertical column (line) of bricks, the higher the column, the greater the pressure on the lower bricks. To build the column higher requires strengthening the lower portions of the column, by increasing its width, or by some other means.

Extend this thought to an area. From the standpoint of empty Euclidean space, an area is that which has length and width. A bounded area is enclosed by a line either straight or curved. A physical area, however, is enclosed by a physical structure, the shape of which is determined by physical principles. One approach to enclosing a physical area, would be to build two vertical columns and span those columns with a flat roof. But, this is a relatively weak structure, as the roof is only strong near where it is supported by the columns. The farther apart the columns are, the weaker is the roof. (See Figure 3.)

Figure 3

A far more stable structure for vaulting a vertical area is an arch. The circle is at first thought the simplest type of arch, because the circular boundary encloses the largest area by the least perimeter. If the arch is designed so that all the bricks point to the center of the circle, the arch will be relatively stable upon completion. (See Figure 4.) But, while under construction, the arch cannot support itself, requiring the use of a temporary scaffolding to support the arch under construction. Thus, the arch is self-supporting as a whole, but not in its parts.

Figure 4

The circular arch poses another problem. Even though it encloses the greatest area with the least perimeter, its height is a function of its width and the line of pressure does not conform to the circular curve. (See Figure 5.)

Figure 5

To enclose a taller area requires a wider arch which in turn decreases the overall stability of the structure because the downward pressure from the upper bricks pushes the sides of the arch outward. Thus, even though, from the standpoint of abstract geometry, the circle is isoperimetric, from the standpoint of physical geometry, some other shape provides the greatest stability for the tallest area. The shape that achieves this is a pointed arch in which the two arcs that make up the arch are circular arcs with different centers. (See Figure 6.) The pointed arch, thus, not only encloses a taller area, but is more stable because the curvature of the arch conforms more closely to the physical line of stresses in the structure. In other words, the shape of the arch is determined not by abstract geometrical characteristics but by physical ones.

Figure 6

Now, to the problem facing Brunelleschi enclosing a volume. Geometrically, a volume is enclosed by a surface, which is produced when a curve is moved. For example, from the famous construction of Archytas, when a circle is moved along a line, a cylinder is produced; when rotated around a point, a torus is produced; and when rotated around a line, a sphere is produced. And so, a dome can be produced by rotating an arch, either circular or pointed around an axis. (See Figure 7.)

Figure 7

But, a physical surface, such as a dome, is not simply a rotated arch, because a new set of stresses occurs in the dome that does not occur in the arch. In addition to the stresses along the arch, (from top to bottom, i.e., longitudinal), there are stresses around the dome (circumferential or hoop).

So, the problem Brunelleschi faced in building the Dome of the required size was to design a structure whose shape would balance these stresses without requiring external buttressing which would diminish the Dome’s beauty and undermine its effectiveness for changing society by changing the minds of the population.

Additionally, a dome, like an arch, generally requires a supporting scaffold, or centering, to hold it up until its completion. Here, Brunelleschi faced his most formidable obstacle. The Dome over Santa Maria del Fiore was so big that there was not enough wood available to build such a large scaffolding. Consequently, Brunelleschi took the bold step of building the Dome without centering, requiring him to construct a dome that was self-supporting in its whole and its parts. Such a shape could not be determined by the methods associated with Euclidean geometry. The shape Brunelleschi required was determined only by physical principles.

To do this, Brunelleschi decided to construct two domes, one inside the other, with a stairway between them. Both would conform to the pointed arch form called for in the original design. However, according to the architect Bartoli, (see 1989 21st Century) the curve of the inner dome was a based on a circle whose diameter was three fourths the inside diameter of the octagonal drum (pointed fourth) while the outer dome’s curvature was four-fifths the outer diameter (a pointed fifth) (See Figure 8.)

Figure 8

Since the use of centering had to be avoided, Brunelleschi had to control the curvature of both domes very carefully as the were being constructed. This entailed controlling three different curvatures: the longitudinal curvature; the circumferential curvature; and the curvature inward towards the center of the Dome. If all three curvatures could be controlled during all phases of construction, the Dome would not only be stable upon completion, but each stage would be stable enough to be a platform from which the next stage would be built. Thus, the Dome had to conform to a shape that would be self-supporting in its whole and its parts.

Brunelleschi had to solve a multitude of problems, each requiring revolutionary new ideas to accomplish the task. But, the discovery most central to his success, the one most relevant for the future development of the anti-Euclidean physical geometry of Kepler, Fermat, Leibniz, Gauss and Riemann, is the one identified by LaRouche. Brunelleschi used a hanging chain to guide the development of the curvature of the dome at each stage of construction. Thus, the overall shape of the Dome was determined, not by a curvature defined by abstract mathematics, but by a physically defined principle. Just as a hanging chain is self-supporting in its whole and its parts, the Dome, whose curvature is guided by the curvature of the hanging chain, is, likewise, self-supporting surface, in its whole and its parts.

The beauty of the Dome demonstrates the truth of Brunelleschi’s discovery, but, it would take the discoveries of Kepler, Fermat, Leibniz, Gauss, Riemann and LaRouche to fully grasp the underlying principle.

The Development of the Physical Idea of Shape

The success of Brunelleschi’s Dome demonstrated that the architectural principles of physical geometry on which it was based were universal. This view was expressed by Johannes Kepler, who approximately 150 years later wrote concerning the construction of the solar system in his Mysterium Cosmographicum, “We perceive how God, like one of our own architects, approached the task of constructing the universe with order and pattern, and laid out the individual parts accordingly, as if it were not art which imitated Nature, but God himself had looked to the mode of building of Man who was to be.”

Kepler went on to develop, in that work and in his subsequent New Astronomy and Harmonies of the World, that the shape of the solar system, like the Dome, was determined not by considerations of abstract mathematics, (which would have indicated perfectly circular orbits) but by physically determined harmonic principles. Thus, the elliptical planetary orbits, like Brunelleschi’s Dome, were the size and shape that they had to be in order to express the harmonic relationships of those physical principles.

This physically determined idea of shape took another step in its development with Fermat’s determination that the shape of the pathway of light was determined by the principle of shortest-time:

“Our demonstration is based on the single postulate, that Nature operates by the most easy and convenient methods and pathways — as it is in this way that we think the postulate should be stated, and not, as usually is done, by saying that Nature always operates by the shortest lines … We do not look for the shortest spaces or lines, but rather those that can be traversed in the easiest way, most conveniently and in the shortest time.”

Leibniz, following up on the discoveries of Kepler and Fermat, generalized these discoveries as a universal principle of least-action:

“…the Architect of all things created light in such a way that this most beautiful result is born from its very nature. That is the reason why those who, like Descartes, reject the existence of Final Causes in Physics, commit a very big mistake, to say the least; because aside from revealing the wonders of divine wisdom, such final causes make us discover a very beautiful principle, along with the properties of such things whose intimate nature is not yet that clearly perceived by us, that we can have the power to explain them, and make use of their efficient causes, along with their artifacts, such as the Creator employed them in order to produce their results, and to determine their ends. It must be further understood from this that the meditations of the ancients on such matters are not to be taken lightly, as certain people think nowadays.”

Leibniz’ most far reaching discovery of this principle of least-action, made in collaboration with Johann Bernoulli, demonstrated that the catenary, the guiding principle of Brunelleschi’s Dome, embodied the most universal expression of least-action. As we’ve developed in other locations, the physical characteristic by which the hanging chain supports itself, expresses all the elementary transcendental relationships of geometry: the circular, hyperbolic, and the powers associated with lines, surfaces and volumes. (See Figure 9.)

Figure 9

Look back at our earlier comparison of the difference between abstract geometrical notions of line, area and volume, with the physical requirements of constructing a column, arch and dome. As is already implicit in the concept of powers developed by Pythagoras, Archytas, Plato, et al., even the purely geometrical concepts of line, area and volume are ultimately determined by the physical principles which Leibniz demonstrated are expressed by the catenary. The idea of lines, areas and volumes, separated from this idea of power as universal physical principles, is as chimerical as the mystical powers of the Roman Pantheon.

From Pathways to Surfaces

Brunelleschi’s Dome points the way to a still further development of the universal principle of least-action. Planetary orbits, the curvature of light, and catenaries are all pathways, i.e. curves. Brunelleschi’s Dome is a least-action surface.

The concepts to understand this distinction were developed by Gauss who, looking back as we’ve been doing, on the discoveries of Kepler, Fermat and Leibniz, developed the foundations of a physical theory of surfaces.

The context for Gauss’ discovery was his measurement of the surface of the Earth, which, because it is physically determined, must, in keeping with Leibniz’ principle, be a least-action surface. Over a more than 20 year period, Gauss made careful astronomical and geodetical measurements of the Earth. Abstract geometrical considerations would suggest that the Earth would be a perfect sphere, because the sphere enclosed the largest volume inside the smallest surface. But, because the Earth is a rotating body in the solar system, its physical shape is not spherical, but ellipsoidal.

As we have developed in earlier pedagogicals, Gauss’ measurements led him to discover that the physical shape of the Earth was not ellipsoidal, but something more irregular. He identified the, “geometrical shape of the Earth, as that shape which is everywhere perpendicular to the pull of gravity.” In other words, Gauss did not try to fit the Earth into a shape pulled from the text books of abstract mathematics, rather, he invented a new geometry that conformed to the physical characteristics of the rotating Earth.

Gauss reported the generalization of his discoveries in his 1822 Copenhagen Prize Essay, on conformal representation and his 1827, “General Investigations of Curved Surfaces”. Future pedagogicals will develop these concepts in greater detail, while here we focus on the general ideas most relevant to this discussion.

For Gauss, all surfaces had a characteristic curvature, which in turn determined certain least-action pathways, that he later called, “geodesics”. For example, in a plane, the geodesic is a straight-line, while on a sphere, the geodesic is a great circle. In these two cases the curvature is uniform and so the geodesic is the same every where on the surface. In contrast, an ellipsoid, for example, is a surface of non-uniform curvature. Consequently, the geodesic is different depending on its direction and position on the surface. (See Figure 10.)

Figure 10

To illustrate this, the reader is encouraged to do some physical experiments. Take a plane, sphere, spaghetti squash or other irregular shaped object. Mark two points at different places on the surface and stretch a thread between them so that the thread is taught. The thread will conform approximately to the geodesic between those two points. Notice that on the plane, the geodesic is always a straight line, while on the sphere it is always a great circle, while on the squash, the geodesic changes from place to place, and direction to direction.

There is a further distinction between the plane and the sphere or ellipsoid. On the plane there are an infinite number of pathways between any two points, but only one of these paths is a geodesic, i.e. least-action. This is also true on a sphere or ellipsoid, except, if the two points are at the poles. Then there are an infinite number of geodesics between these two points. Thus, the bounded nature of the sphere and ellipsoid, produce a singularity with respect to the nature of the geodesics. The significance of this distinction will become more clear as we develop more of Riemann’s geometry in future pedagogicals.

What Gauss investigated was the general principles by which the curvature of the surface determined the characteristic of the geodesic. Of immediate relevance for this discussion is Gauss’ determination of a means to measure the curvature of the surface at any point. It is sufficient for our purposes here to illustrate this by a physical demonstration. On the squash, draw a circle by tying a marker to one end of the thread and rotating it while holding the other end of the thread in a fixed position. The radii of this circle are all geodesics in different directions. Now examine the curvature of each geodesic, which will vary for each direction. However, one geodesic will be the least curved, while another will be the most curved. Now, try this on a different type of surface, such as a butternut squash shaped like a dumbbell. The part of the round ends of the butternut squash have the same characteristic as the spaghetti squash, in that the center of curvature is always inside the squash. But, in the middle of the squash something different happens. Here the center of curvature is either inside or outside the squash, depending on the direction of the geodesic. This characteristic Gauss called, “negative curvature” and is the characteristic of curvature expressed by a surface formed by a rotated catenary called a catenoid. (See Figure 11.)

Figure 11

Brunelleschi’s Dome expresses this characteristic of negative curvature.

Furthermore, Gauss proved that on any surface, no matter how irregularly it was curved, the geodesics of maximum and minimum curvature would always be at right angles to each other!

Thus, at any place on a surface, the curvature of the surface expresses a physical principle that in turn determines the geodesic, or least-action pathway within that surface.

From Surfaces to Manifolds

Working from Gauss’ discovery, Riemann generalized this concept still further to the idea of a geodesic within a manifold of universal physical principles. The manifolds cannot be directly visualized but the characteristics of that manifold can be directly determined by a change in geodesic.

For example, light under reflection and refraction follows a pathway within a surface, but each type of action expresses a different pathway because the physical manifold of refraction includes a principle, changing speed of light, that does not exist within the manifold of reflection. The addition of this new principle to the manifold of action, changes the geodesic.

Riemann developed the means to represent these higher manifolds by complex functions. For example, as was developed in the previous pedagogical, the conic section orbits and catenary are both least-action pathways with respect to the manifold of universal gravitation. In other words, each represents a changing geodesic with the manifold of universal gravitation. But, when the catenary is expressed as a function in the Gauss/Riemann complex domain, the conic section orbits are seen as a subsumed geodesic within the higher principle represented by the catenary. (See Riemann for Anti-Dummies Part 40.)

More general examples are illustrated in the accompanying animations. These illustrate how the same action, when carried out in different manifolds, is changed by the characteristics of the manifold. Think of the orthogonal nets in each figure as the minimum and maximum geodesics in each manifold. The loopy curve maintains the same angular orientation with respect to these geodesics in each case. But, because the geodesics change, from manifold to manifold, the action changes. Thus, a change in the principles that determine the manifold, change the geodesics, which in turn change all action within that manifold. Conversely, to effect a physical change in any action, one must act to change the characteristics of the manifold.

z2

z3

ez

1/z

Catenary

Now look at Brunelleschi’s Dome from this standpoint. The Dome is a surface whose geodesic, in principle, conforms to the catenary. As a least-action surface, it expresses a geodesic with respect to the principle of universal gravitation. With respect to the manifold of universal history, building the Dome was the geodesic from that dying culture of the Roman Empire to the Renaissance.

At our present place in the manifold of universal history, building LaRouche’s youth movement combat university on wheels and making LaRouche President of the United States, is for us, Brunelleschi’s Dome– the geodesic from this dark age to our Renaissance.

Riemann for Anti-Dummies: Part 40 : Cognitive Least Action

Riemann for Anti-Dummies Part 40

COGNITIVE LEAST ACTION

Throughout his various works on complex functions, Riemann notes that the hidden harmonies of the complex domain, not calculations, are the least action pathways for the discovery of truth.

Riemann’s concept is in keeping with the tradition from Plato to Gauss, as exemplified by Gauss’ determination of the orbit of Ceres. In that case, every leading astronomer attempted to deduce Ceres’ orbit by an ever increasing level of calculations upon the few data points of observations supplied by Piazzi. All failed. Gauss, on the other hand, focused on Kepler’s harmonic principles, finding Ceres’ orbit as a consequence of them. Where the failures calculated unknown data from known data, Gauss sought the principles that determined both the known and unknown data. Gauss later distinguished his method from the failed ones with reference to Euler’s famous attempt to deduce the orbit of a comet by detailed calculation, an effort that left Euler blind in one eye. “I too would have gone blind,” Gauss is reported to have said, “If I calculated like Euler did.”

As urgent and necessary as it is for political leaders to grasp Gauss’ and Riemann’s method, it nonetheless presents serious psychological difficulties for those reared in the fantasy world of the post-1966 consumer society. As noted in last week’s installment, consumers only know objects and how to manipulate them. Acting on the world is limited to manipulating those objects according to a set of authoritative rules. Consumers look in awe to those other consumers who appear to manipulate the greatest number of objects. (Modern academics call this objective science.) It is no wonder that under conditions of systemic collapse, such consumers become fear-driven pessimists.

Yet, to act on the world as Gauss and Riemann did, requires a capacity of mind to grasp not things, but relationships. Not merely relations among things, but relationships among sets of relations. This, as Gauss and Riemann demonstrated, is the province of the complex domain.

To further illustrate this point, look at the principle of universal gravitation. As a principle, universal gravitation is not expressible by a number, such as 32/feet/second/second. Nor is it expressible by an algebraic formula such as the inverse square law. Principles, to be truly comprehended, can only be known by how they act on other principles. As such, principles must be thought of only by Riemann’s concept of a manifold. Under Riemann’s idea of a complex function, the mind acts, not on things, but on manifolds of principles.

This concept is well developed by Kepler’s succession of discoveries with regard to planetary motion, from the astronomical significance of the Platonic solids, to the elliptical orbits, to the harmonic proportions among the orbits. Each of the above principles expresses a set of relations. Universal gravitation expresses the relationship among these sets of relations.

The Leibniz/Bernoulli principle of the catenary similarly expresses a set of relations, ordered by the principle of universal gravitation. As will be illustrated below, the complex domain affords us the power to comprehend the unifying relationship of universal gravitation between these two sets of seemingly different relations.

Before exploring more specifically the manifold of universal gravitation, it were beneficial to engage in a short warm-up exercise. Look again at a simple example of a complex function, for example, the complex function that corresponds to the general principle of doubling the square. (See figure 1a, figure 1b, and figure 1c.)

Figure 1a

Figure 1b

Figure 1c

Use this example to begin to wrench your mind away from the consumerist fixation on things, so as to be able to better grasp the physical example that will follow. In this example, think of the orthogonal grid of lines depicted on the left side of 1b not as a collection of lines and points, but as a metaphorical representation of a set of ideas related to each other in that way. Each idea is represented by a complex number, which denotes a unique action. (That action is always with respect to some origin, which is always defined by some physical singularity.) The lines connecting the points can be thought of, metaphorically, as least action pathways, i.e. geodesics, with respect to the principle of organization of the manifold of ideas represented.

Now, a new principle is introduced, in this example the principle of doubling the square. The introduction of that principle transforms all the straight-line relationships into parabolic pathways. The introduction of such a new principle, transforms all the relationships of the manifold, all at once, without, so to speak, calculation. To properly grasp this conception, resist the tendency to think of the grid of lines as a thing and the grid of parabolic pathways as another thing. Rather, think of one manifold– a polyphony evoked by the introduction of the new principle of squaring, which changes the “geodesic” within each set of relations. (See animation 1.)

Animation 1

Armed with this warm up, move on, to a physical example:

What is the connection, with respect to the principle of universal gravitation, between the least action pathway expressed by the catenary and the least action pathways expressed by the conic section planetary orbits of Kepler and Gauss? This can only be grasped from the standpoint of the complex domain.

Begin with Leibniz’ discovery that the catenary expresses the arithmetic mean between two exponential (logarithmic) functions. (See figure 2.)

This is already a precursor of Riemann’s idea of a complex function. Think of each exponential not as a “graph” as you were taught in school, but, as, Leibniz did, as a relationship of two relationships, the arithmetic and the geometric. (See figure 3.) Thus, the catenary expresses a relationship between two sets of arithmetic-geometric (exponential/logarithmic) relations.

Figure 3

But, as Riemann noted, when this relationship among sets of relations is viewed from the standpoint of the complex domain, “a regularity and harmony emerge that otherwise remain hidden.”

Look, first, at the exponential/logarithmic relationship in the complex domain. To do this, we must think, as Gauss did, of the complex domain as represented by a doubly-extended surface, with a physically determined origin, in this case, the lowest point of the catenary. Each point on the surface represents a complex number which itself denotes a unique exponential action. (See figure 4.)

Figure 4

Complex numbers represented by points equally spaced along a line are related to each other arithmetically. Complex numbers represented by points along a spiral, are related to each other geometrically. Thought of in this way, a grid of lines expresses an arithmetic relationship between complex exponentials. (See figure 5.)

Figure 5

The points along any one line are arithmetically related complex numbers. Lines that are equally spaced to other lines, (such as those in the grid) are arithmetically related sets of arithmetically related complex numbers.

Now, take this relationship so described, and use that as a principle of transformation of the complex domain itself. (See animation 2.)

Animation 2

This transformation expresses, from the higher standpoint of the complex domain., the relationship between the arithmetic and geometric that was otherwise previously expressed by Leibniz, et al. with respect to exponential, circular and hyperbolic functions. The complex exponential transforms the arithmetic relationships into geometric ones, creating a sort of arithmetic-geometric relationship among arithmetic-geometric relationships. Here, the arithmetically related (equal spaced), vertical lines become circles whose radii are geometrically related. The points along each line that are arithmetically related (equally spaced) become equally spaced points along the arcs of the circles. Inversely, the arithmetically related (equally spaced) horizontal lines become equally spaced radii, while the arithmetically related (equally spaced) points along each horizontal line, become geometrically related points along each radii. (See figure 6.)

Figure 6

When one considers the circles as special cases of spirals, the equally spaced radii and equally spaced points along the arcs are also in geometric relationship to each other as well.

Now take the next step, and apply Leibniz’ principle of the catenary as the arithmetic mean between two exponentials in this complex domain. The arithmetic mean between two inversely related circles forms an ellipse. (See animation 3.)

Animation 3

The arithmetic mean between two inversely related radii forms an hyperbola. ( See animation 4.)

Animation 4

The totality of this transformation forms an orthogonal array of ellipses and hyperbolas which correspond to the least-action pathways of the catenary in the complex domain. (See figure 7, and animation 5.)

Figure 7

Animation 5

Thus, Leibniz’ catenary principle, expressed in the complex domain of Gauss and Riemann expresses a manifold of elliptical and hyperbolic least-action pathways. In other words, the complex domain, as that domain in which we can represent as shadows, the manifold of relationships among sets relationships, increases the cognitive power of the mind, such that we become able to comprehend universal gravitation, as a principle of unity of least action among the catenary and conic section planetary orbits, and, of course, much, much, more.

Riemann for Anti-Dummies: Part 39

Riemann For Anti-Dummies Part 39

To paraphrase Nicholas of Cusa, consumers, like animals, don’t count. They have no concept of number. Their mental world is made up only of the things they consume. How those things are produced, what power generates such things, is beyond their ken. Numbers, for them, are mere symbols, that, when manipulated according to a learned set of authoritative rules, (such as the rules of money), have some unexplainable, but psychologically powerful, connection to the things they consume.Such numbers don’t count.

“Number”, according to Cusa, is, “unfolded reason … theprime exemplar of the mind”. In the Pythagorean tradition of Plato, Cusa recognized that numbers don’t count things. Number is the means by which the mind comprehends relations. Not simple relationships among things, but the relationships among relationships. “We conjecture metaphorically from the rational numbers of our mind in respect to the real ineffable numbers of the divine Mind, we indeed say that number is the prime exemplar of things in the mind of the Composer, just as the number arising from our rationality is the exemplar of the imaginal world.”

This capacity is a unique human characteristic and is bound up with man’s capacity to increase his power in and over the universe. As Prometheus states in Aeschylus’ drama, Man was, “in an ignorant condition, living in holes and– … utterly without knowledge, until I taught them to discern the rising of the stars and their settings, which are difficult to distinguish. Yes, and numbers, too, chiefest of sciences, I invented for them, and the combining of letters, creative mother of the Muses’ arts, with which to hold all things in memory….”

This is the concept of number specific to a healthy producer society. For the consumer milk comes from the supermarket. There is no concept of number associated with this idea other than the symbol appearing on the display of the cash register in response to a computer scanning of a bar code. Contrast this to the numbers that express the relationship of that milk in the supermarket to the dairy farm and transportation system that produced the milk and transported it to the store. Now, think of the higher concept of number associated with the multiply-connected manifold of abiotic, biotic, and cognitive processes that comprise the physical economic relationships of the above transaction. Think still higher of the numbers associated with the multi-generational trajectory in which that multiply-connected physical economic manifold resides. And, still higher to the numbers associated with the manifold of universal principles — those discovered and those still yet to be discovered — which have the power to change that trajectory and all that follows from it.

The productive power of the mind counts, and it counts with complex numbers.

To grasp the concept of complex numbers requires the mind be wrenched away from those neurotic, consumerist tendencies that associate numbers with sensible objects. For that reason, a careful study of Gauss’ “Disquisitiones Arithmeticae” is highly recommended, as anyone who has had the pleasure of unfolding its wisdom will attest. By the time Gauss composed this opus, at the age of 22, he had already a fully-developed concept of the complex domain, as indicated in the climactic seventh section on the division of the circle. That section, although last in the book, was written first, and the principles expressed there unfold from the opening motivic idea of the work Gauss’ concept of congruence.

Gauss generalizes Kepler’s notion of harmony by establishing numbers with respect to their intervallic relationship, as distinct from the sense-certainty concept of things. Illustrate this idea (as we have in past pedagogicals) with a simple example. Draw five dots in roughly a circle. Label these dots 0, 1, 2, 3, 4, respectively. Now, connect these dots in sequence. Call that sequence 1. Next, connect every other dot. Call that sequence 2. Next, connect every third dot. Call that sequence 3. The same with every fourth dot. Connecting every fifth dot leads nowhere. Now, try every sixth, seventh, etc.

Calling five a modulus, Gauss’ concept of congruence establishes each number by its relationship to all other numbers with respect to modulus five. You should have noticed that sequence 1 and 6, 2 and 7, 3 and 8, etc. produced the same results. Such relationships were called by Gauss “congruent with respect to modulus five”. (The difference between two congruent numbers is equal to the modulus.) Also, sequence 2 produced the same result as sequence 3, except in opposite direction. A similar relationship was produced for 1 and 4. Introducing “-“to denote direction, Gauss’ congruence is also expressed by the relationships of 1 to -4; 4 to -1; 2 to -3; and 3 to -2.

Think back over this simple exercise. The numbers0, 1, 2, 3, 4, -1, -2, -3, -4, always denote relationships, not things. The initial numbers, 0, 1, 2, 3, 4, denote the relationship of each individual dot to all five. The sequence numbers, both positive and negative, denote relationships among these relationships.

Thus, the modulus, in this case five, denotes not five things, but a type of intervallic relationship among relationships. Inversely, the domain of such relationships denotes five as a prime number, as it establishes a total number of relationships equal to 5 minus 1. (It is suggested the reader try the above experiment with moduli 6, 7, 8, 9, 10, 11 to establish this concept more fully in your mind.)

Underlying these relationships is the “dimensionality” of the domain in which they arise. Each number and each sequence followed its predecessor by the same difference by which it was followed by its successor, i.e., arithmetically. Now, extend this investigation into a doubly-connected, i.e., geometric, domain. To do this think of 1,2,3,4 as sides of squares. 1 and4 produce squares of area 1 and 16 respectively, which, with respect to modulus five are both congruent to 1. 2 and 3 produce squares of 4 and 9 respectively, which with respect to modulus 5are congruent to -1. Thus, with respect to modulus 5, both 1 and-1 are squares! 1 and 4 are ?1, and 2 and 3 are ?-1 modulo 5! For this and related reasons, Gauss insisted that ?-1 be given “full civil rights” with all other numbers, and the domain of numbers should be extended to include them.

“The mathematician always abstracts from the constitution of objects and the content of their relations. He is only concerned with counting and comparing these relations; in this sense he is entitled to extend the characteristic of similarity which he ascribes to the relations denoted by +1 and -1 to all four elements +1, -1, i (?-1) and -i (-?-1),” Gauss wrote in the announcement to his second treatise on biquadratic residues.

Gauss insisted, and repeatedly stated, that this, “complex domain” was a higher concept that existed outside the domain of the senses, but, “the true metaphysics of these magnitudes could be placed in a most excellent light”, by representing these relationships as a quadratic array on a doubly extended surface:

“To form a concrete picture of these relationships it is necessary to construct a spatial representation, and the simplest case is, where no reason exists for ordering the symbols for the objects in any other way that in a quadratic array, to divide an unbounded plane into squares by two systems of parallel lines, and chose as symbols the intersection points of the lines. Every such point A has four neighbors, and if the relation of A to one of the neighboring points is denoted by +1, then the point corresponding to -1 is automatically determined, while we are free to choose either one of the remaining two neighboring points, to the left or to the right, as defining the relation to be denoted by + i. This distinction between right and left is, once one has arbitrarily chosen forwards and backwards in the plane, and upward and downward in relation to the two sides of the plane, in and of itself completely determined, even though we are able to communicate our concept of this distinction to other persons only by referring to actually existing material objects.*

[* Kant already had made both of these remarks, but we cannot understand how this sharp-witted philosopher could have seen in the first remark a proof of his opinion, that space is only a form of our external perception, when in fact the second remark proves the opposite, namely that space must have a real meaning outside of our mode of perception.]

“The difficulty, one has believed, that surrounds the theory of imaginary magnitudes, is based in large part to that not so appropriate designation (it has even had the discordant name impossible magnitude imposed on it). Had one started from the idea to present a manifold of two dimensions (which presents the conception of space with greater clarity), the positive magnitudes would have been called direct, the negative inverse, and the imaginary lateral, so there would be simplicity instead of confusion, clarity instead of darkness,” Gauss wrote in his second treatise on biquadratic residues.

Thought of in this way, each complex number denotes a two-fold complex of direct and lateral action, or, rotation and extension. The physical example Gauss gave for this relationship was the motion of the bubble in a plane leveller. The bubble could only move back and forth if the ends of the level moved up and down.

Gauss’ idea of complex numbers extends his concept of congruence, by which the relationships among numbers are grasped, to the complex domain, by which relationships among a set of relations can be comprehended. Just as his earlier concept of a modulus expressed a simple intervallic relationship among numbers, the complex modulus expressed a complex interval. (See figure 1a, and figure 1b.)

Riemann for Anti-Dummies: Part 38 : You Are Not Impossible

Riemann for Anti-Dummies Part 38

YOU ARE NOT IMPOSSIBLE

When Gauss set about writing his 1799 dissertation on what he called, “The Fundamental Theorem of Algebra,” he had already in his mind a fully developed concept of the complex domain as the idea that penetrated most deeply into the metaphysics of space, and he would spend the rest of his life unfolding the implications of that youthful discovery. But, in order to achieve what he would later call, “full civil rights for complex numbers,” he first had to root out the source of their oppression: the popular acceptance of Euler’s diktat that such numbers were “impossible.”

What one considers “impossible” is, fundamentally, a function of one’s concept of what is “possible.” Think of the foolishness today of those who insist that what Lyndon LaRouche says must be done, (most emphatically his electability as President of the United States) is “impossible.” Their tragic mistake flows not from any reasoned, scientific assessment of the matter. They assert its impossibility because they don’t want to face the possibility that their continued existence is possible only if what they think is “impossible” actually happens.

In one of his epistemological fragments, Bernhard Riemann spoke of the significance of the possible for science:

“Natural science is the attempt to understand nature by means of exact concepts.

“According to the concepts through which we comprehend nature our perceptions are supplemented and filled in, not simply at each moment, but also future perceptions are seen as necessary. Or, to the degree that the conceptual system is not fully sufficient, future perceptions are determined beforehand as probable; according to the concepts, what is “possible” is determined (thus what is `necessary’ and conversely, impossible). And the degree of possibility (of `probability’) of each individual event which is seen as possible, in light of these concepts, can be mathematically determined, if the concepts are precise enough.

“To the extent that what is necessary or probable, according to these concepts, takes place, then this confirms the concepts, and the trust that we place in these concepts rests on this confirmation through experience. But, if something takes place that is unexpected according to our existing assumptions, i.e. that is impossible or improbable according to them, then the task arises of completing them or, if necessary reworking the axioms, so that what is perceived ceases to be impossible or, improbable. The completion or improvement of the conceptual system forms the `explanation’ of the unexpected perception. Our comprehension of nature gradually becomes more and more complete and correct through this process, simultaneously penetrating more and more behind the surface of appearances.

“The history of causal natural science, in so far as we can trace it back, shows that this is, in fact, the way our knowledge of nature advances. The conceptual systems that are now the basis for the natural sciences, arose through a gradual transformation of older conceptual systems, and the reasons that drove us to new modes of explanation can always be traced back to contradictions and improbabilities that emerged from the older modes of explanation.”

By maintaining the “impossibility” of complex numbers, Euler, (whose patrons were the enemies of the American Revolution), along with J.L. Lagrange, (Napoleon’s favorite mathematician), sought not merely to exclude such magnitudes from mathematical calculations. Both Euler and Lagrange made liberal use of these “impossible” magnitudes in formal calculations. Rather, Euler et al. sought to exclude the possibility that the human mind could penetrate beneath the surface of appearances into the deeper domain of, what Plato called “powers,” where complex numbers arise.

In his 1799 dissertation Gauss attacked Euler’s method directly:

“If imaginary quantities are to be retained in analysis at all (which seems for several reasons more advisable than to abolish them, once they are established in a solid manner), then they must necessarily be considered equally possible as real quantities; for which reason I would like to comprise the reals and the imaginaries under the common denomination of {possible quantities}: Against which I would call {impossible} a quantity that would have to fulfill conditions that could not even be fulfilled by allowing imaginaries.”

The existence of complex numbers was not only possible: It was necessary to comprehend what ultimately made all numbers possible.

To establish this, Gauss tapped into the deep vein of investigations that goes all the way back to the Pythagoreans, who understood number as the means by which the mind expresses the harmonic principles that lie beneath the shadow of sense perception.

Writing in “On Learned Ignorance,” Nicholas of Cusa described this concept of number this way:

“All those who investigate, judge the uncertain by comparing it to a supposed by a system of proportions…. But the proportion which expresses agreement in one aspect and difference in another, cannot be understood without number. That is why number embraces everything which is susceptible of proportions. Thus, it not only creates proportion in quantity, but in every respect through which, by substance or accident, (two things) might agree and disagree. Thus, Pythagoras rigorously concluded that everything is constituted and comprehended through the power of numbers.”

Number has the power to express powers through proportions. Complex numbers express proportions among powers.

For example, the power to double a square is expressed through the geometric proportion 1, 2, 4, 8, 16, 32, etc., even though the magnitude that doubles the square is incommensurable to all these numbers. Furthermore, the power that doubles the cube is also expressed, but in a different way, by the same proportion, (as two geometric means between two extremes instead of one), even though the magnitude that doubles the cube is also incommensurable to all those numbers.

From this standpoint, all numbers can be generated by a succession of powers, and this is what is meant by the term, “logarithm”–a term coined by John Napier in 1594 from the Greek words “logos” and “arithmos.”

The most general form of this concept is expressed by Jakob Bernoulli’s equiangular spiral and Huygens’ hyperbola. In the former, all possible magnitudes are expressed by the radii whose lengths are a function of an angle of rotation. Proportional lengths correspond to equal angles (see Figure 1).

Figure 1

In the latter, all possible magnitudes are expressed by lengths along the asymptote that correspond to equal areas (see Figure2).

Figure 2

In both cases all possible positive quantities are expressed, inversely, as a function of a power, expressed as either an angle (spiral) or an area (hyperbola).

In both cases, adding the logarithm (angle or area) produces proportional changes in length.

As discussed in the previous installment of this series, Leibniz brought a crucial contradiction to light by posing the question, “What has the power to produce a negative number?” This provoked a dispute with his collaborator Johann Bernoulli, who insisted that negative numbers were produced by the same powers as positive numbers. Leibniz, on the other hand, correctly disagreed. For Leibniz the very existence of negative numbers (which had been called “false” numbers) demanded a higher principle, which Gauss later discovered as the complex domain.

For Gauss, negative numbers were not absolute quantities. They were physically determined. In numerous locations, Gauss repeatedly polemicized, (against I. Kant) that the difference between positive and negative, right and left, up and down, could not be determined by mathematics but only with reference to physical action.

Look at this from the standpoint of the above illustrations of the spiral and hyperbola. Both generate all possible magnitudes as a function of powers. But, in both cases, the exact same result can be obtained, but in exactly the opposite orientation (see Figure 3 and Figure 4). In Figure 3, you can see two spirals that produce the same magnitudes, but in different directions.

Figure 3

In Figure 4 you can see two branches of an hyperbola that produce the same magnitudes, but in different directions.

Figure 4

In each case, if one set of magnitudes is denoted positive numbers the other set can be denoted negative. But, as Gauss pointed out, there is no {a priori} way to distinguish one from the other. Only when presented with both, is the existence of positive and negative established.

But, there is a still deeper, much more profound principle embedded in this. Look at the transition between the positive and negative hyperbola. The vertical asymptote is an “infinite” boundary separating positive from negative. Similarly, for the spirals. The transition from the positive to the negative spiral is the point of the change in direction, which each spiral approaches, but never crosses.

Thus, the domain in which both positive and negative numbers exist together must be of a higher power, where the powers that generate powers reside. It comprises Gauss’ domain of all possible (complex) quantities.

Like all ideas, Gauss recognized that this domain could not be seen directly, but, it, nevertheless, was susceptible of metaphorical representation. Since it was the domain of powers, it could not be represented by simple proportions among things, but as a proportion between proportions. Consequently, each complex number represented a proportion, not a quantity. The manifold of complex numbers, Gauss said, could only be represented on a surface extended in two directions. The physical example Gauss used was the geodesist’s plane leveller. The position of the bubble at rest is determined by both the axis of the tube and the direction of the pull of gravity, which is perpendicular to it.

On Gauss’ surface each point represented a power that was denoted by a complex number. Using some physically determined point and line as a reference, each power, i.e., each complex number is generated by a spiral action rotation and extension (see Figure 5).

Figure 5

In this way, proportions between proportions could be represented.

For example, a power acting on a power. In Figure 6 and Animation 1, complex number a+bi represents a power produced by a combination of rotation and extension. When that power acts on itself, it produces (a+bi)2. When it acts on itself again it produces (a+bi)3, etc. What results is a series of similar triangles conforming to an equiangular spiral. While this spiral looks similar to Bernoulli’s spiral, it is different. Bernoulli’s spiral represents a succession of powers that produce simple magnitudes. Gauss’ complex spiral represents a higher power that produces a succession of powers, not simple magnitudes.

Figure 6

Animation 1

Figure 7, illustrates the more general case of the proportion between two different powers, or, what is commonly known as multiplication. Here the complex number 2 + i is multiplied by 1 + 2i to form 5i. In this case the 2 + i forms the red triangle with vertices 0, 1, 2 + i. The product is the point (5i) which forms the similar triangle with 0, 1 + 2i as its base. (The schoolbook arithmetic idea of multiplication as a set of rules is brainwashing. As Gauss emphasized, multiplication is a proportion such that 1: a :: b: a x b. You, the reader, are left to confirm this for yourself experimentally. Try experimenting with Theatetus’ squares and rectangles.)

Figure 7

As in the previous examples of the hyperbola and spiral, the proportional changes in extension are “connected” by adding the angles (logarithm) and multiplying the lengths.

Riemann for Anti-Dummies: Part 37 : The Domain of Possibility

RIEMANN FOR ANTI-DUMMIES PART 37

THE DOMAIN OF POSSIBILITY

Plato, speaking in the Laws through the voice of an Athenian stranger, holds it indispensable for leaders of society to possess elaborate knowledge of arithmetic, astronomy and the mensuration of lines, surfaces and solids. He also considers it a disgrace for any common man to lack a basic understanding of these same subjects.

It is altogether fitting that these words should issue from someone far from home, for, as Helga Zepp-LaRouche so artfully demonstrated in her presentation to the ICLC Labor Day Conference, by the time of Plato’s writing ,Athenian culture had estranged itself from these concerns and embarked on that chain of events which led to the disastrous Peloponnesian Wars. It is further fitting that Plato speaks here as a stranger, as all three subjects share a common focus on the exploration of those universal principles that govern, but don’t reside, in the domain of objects and sense perception. To one trapped in the domain of the senses, those principles appear to come from some foreign land “over the horizon”, or, “beyond the finite” . But, to one willing to ascend to its not too distant shores, that place is the province from which come the common principles, that make possible such diverse discoveries, as the founding ideas of the American Republic, the Gauss-Riemann concept of the complex domain and Beethoven’s late string quartets.

The Universe is a wondrous, but not a strange place. As Nicholas of Cusa and G.W. Leibniz repeatedly emphasized, nothing exists or happens in the Universe that is not possible. It is the province of science, therefore, to discover what makes things possible. In so doing, the mind discovers not only the possibility of a particular thing, but it also discovers, and changes, the possibility of what it can discover about what is possible. Hence, Plato’s emphasis on the study of the above mentioned subjects. It is both a means to discover what makes these things possible and a pathway for the mind to discover how it is possible for it to discover what is possible, thereby increasing its power.

Proceed through the example of the mensuration of the line, surface and solid. As presented in earlier locations, each object is made possible by a principle that possess the power to produce it. The power to generate the line is different, and incommensurable with, the power that generates a square, which, in turn, is different and incommensurable with, the power to generate a solid. This, in itself, is a crucial discovery. But, the more important discovery comes when the next question is posed. Since all three distinct powers exist in the one Universe, what is it about the Universe that makes possible these three distinct powers?

The answer to this type of question does not lie in the particular nature of each discovery, but in the paradox that one universe produces all three. As Cusa put it in “On Learned Ignorance”:

“All our wisest and most divine teachers agree that visible things are truly images of invisible things and that from created things the Creator can be knowably seen as in a mirror and a metaphor. But the fact that spiritual matters (which are unattainable by us in themselves) are investigated metaphorically has its basis in what was said earlier. For all things have a certain comparative relation to one another, a relation which is nonetheless, hidden from us and incomprehensible to us), so that from out of all things there arises one universe and in this one maximum all things are this one. And although every image seems to be like its exemplar, nevertheless except for the Maximal Image (which is, in oneness of nature, the very thing which its Exemplar is) no image is so similar or equal to its exemplar that it cannot be infinitely more similar and equal…”

The square is bounded by lines, but those lines can only be produced from squares, not from lines alone. The action of doubling a square, as the Pythagoreans discovered, produces a certain harmony which they called geometric. Contained within that geometric series is a reflection of the harmony that doubles the cube, expressed as two geometric means between two extremes, instead of the one geometric mean expressed by the square. But, as the discoveries of Archytus and Menaechmus demonstrate, that “cubic” harmony, although reflected in the process of doubling the square, can only be constructed by a completely different process, that associated with the conic sections. Since the cube can generate a square and a square can generate a line, but not vice versa, all three powers can be understood as flowing from the higher principle of generation expressed by the conic sections. In other words, what makes all three powers possible is not manifest, sensually, in any of them. What makes them all possible is manifest only outside all lines, squares and cubes, in the principle of action exhibited by the conic sections.

Now, begins more fun. What makes the conic sections possible? To answer this question, one must first ferret out the contradictions within the domain of the conic sections. This will take us directly to Gauss’ discovery of the complex domain.

While Greek culture made significant advances in this direction, as exemplified by Apollonius’ Conics, the most significant advance was made by Kepler’s discovery of the projective relationship among the conic sections.

To grasp this, first think of the conic sections, as Apollonius did, as the curves produced by a plane cutting a set of cones joined at their apexes. A plane cutting the lower cone perpendicular to its axis will generate a circle. With the slightest tilt, that circle becomes an ellipse. As the plane’s tilt becomes parallel to the side of the cone, that ellipse becomes a parabola. With the slightest additional tilt, the plane now intersects both cones, forming an hyperbola. The top cone was sitting there all along, but didn’t come into play, until the hyperbola was formed.

From the standpoint of the visual appearance of the cone, all four conic sections are formed by one continuous motion of a plane intersecting with the cones. However, nothing can be discovered from this about what makes this conic manifold possible, unless the cognitive paradoxes, that reside “beyond the finite” are brought more sharply into view, metaphorically.

To do this, Kepler applied the method Cusa states in “On Learned Ignorance”:

“But since from the preceding points it is evident that the unqualifiedly Maximum cannot be any of the things which we either know or conceive: when we set out to investigate the Maximum metaphorically, we must leap beyond simple likeness. For since all mathematicals are finite and otherwise could not even be imagined; if we want to use finite things as a way for ascending to the unqualifiedly Maximum, we must first consider finite mathematical figures together with their characteristics and relations. Next, we must apply these relations, in a transformed way, to corresponding infinite mathematical figures. Thirdly, we must thereafter in a still more highly transformed way, apply the relations of these infinite figures to the simple Infinite, which is altogether independent even of all figures. At this point our ignorance will be taught incomprehensibly how we are to think more correctly and truly about the Most High as we grope by means of metaphor.”

Kepler’s interest in discovering the generating principle of the conic sections was not a matter of mathematical curiosity. His demonstration of the elliptical nature of the planetary orbits demanded a higher comprehension, beyond the simple mathematical relationships within and among the specific curves, of that universal principle (power) which made conic sections possible.

This required him, as Cusa indicated, to consider the finite relationships within and among the conic sections, from the standpoint of the infinite. By projecting the above cited process of a plane cutting a pair of cones onto one flat plane, Kepler brought out the infinite divide between the circle and the hyperbola. From the standpoint of Kepler’s projection, the hyperbola and circle were on opposite sides of the infinite. (See Figure 1.)

Figure 1

With this contradiction brought into view, the stage was set for Fermat, Huygens, Jakob and Johann Bernoulli and Leibniz to bring this paradox up to the point which demanded the discovery the complex domain by Gauss.

This was accomplished by focusing on the significance of this infinite divide between the circle and the hyperbola from the standpoint of the generation of Plato’s powers. On the one side, Jakob Bernoulli demonstrated that the circle, as a special case of an equiangular spiral, expressed the transcendental principle that generated all the so-called algebraic powers as a function of rotation. (See Figure 2.)

Figure 2

On the other side, Huygens demonstrated that the hyperbola expressed that same principle as a function of area and length. (See Figure 3.)

Figure 3

In this contradiction, Leibniz discovered something additional. While the circular principle expressed the transcendental number Pi, the exponential embodied by the hyperbola expressed a different transcendental number, that he called “b”, (later called “e” by Euler). (See Figure 4a and Figure 4b.)

Figure 4a

Figure 4b

Thus, both the circle and the hyperbola expressed, in different ways, a principle that had the power to produce all algebraic powers. Each expressed that power with respect to a different transcendental magnitude. An infinite gap lay between them. The question now posed anew was, what universal principle embodied the higher power that had the potential to generate both distinct transcendentals?

For Leibniz, as for Kepler earlier, this question was not posed as a formal mathematical curiosity. His and Johann Bernoulli’s joint discovery of the catenary demonstrated that the “frozen motion” of the hanging chain, expressed as a physical principle the simultaneous unity of both the trigonometric and exponential transcendentals. (See Figure 5a and Figure 5b.) The catenary, therefore, was the physical expression of a still yet undiscovered domain, that possessed the potential to generate all such transcendental magnitudes.

Figure 5a

Figure 5b

Leibniz understood that this higher domain existed outside the boundaries of the senses. Like all universal principles it could only be known with the mind, and so he referred to it as “imaginary” (not, as Euler would later say, “impossible”). This domain produced artifacts such as the ?-1, which posed a paradox because nothing within the known world could produce a magnitude, which when squared produced -1. Leibniz called ?-1, “a fine and wonderful recourse of the divine spirit, almost an amphibian, somewhere between being and non-being.”

The paradox remains regardless of whether one generates the powers by the spiral or the hyperbola. In the case of the spiral, successive angular rotation produces corresponding increases in the length of the radii of the spiral. The lengths increase by the power that corresponds to the how much the angle of rotation is increased. For example, if the rotation doubles, the length of radius is squared. If the rotation is tripled, the length of the radius is cubed. If the direction of the rotation is reversed, the length of the radii decrease, by the power equivalent to amount of rotation.

Similarly with the hyperbola. Equal areas between the hyperbola and the asymptote correspond to geometric increases in length along the asymptote. Thus, if the area is increased by two, the corresponding length along the asymptote is squared. If the area is increased by three, the corresponding length is cubed, etc. If the area is reduced by half, the corresponding length is reduced by the square root, etc.

So, in the hyperbola the areas change arithmetically while the lengths change geometrically. For the spiral, the angles change arithmetically while the lengths change geometrically. The angles of the spiral, and the areas for the hyperbola, were called by Huygens, Leibniz, and Bernoulli, logarithms.

The paradox posed by Leibniz was this: Since increases or decreases in the logarithms always produce a positive length, “what is the logarithm of a negative number?” or, in other words, what has the power to produce the ?-1.

This provoked a dispute with Johann Bernoulli. Bernoulli maintained that the logarithms of negative numbers were the same as the logarithms of positive numbers. For example, he considered 0 to be the logarithm of 1 and -1, just as 1 and -1 are both square roots of 1. Leibniz, on the other hand, recognized that the same action could not produce 1 and -1.

For Leibniz, this matter could not be resolved within the existing domain of accepted mathematical formalism, just as Gauss would demonstrate in his investigation of the fundamental theorem of algebra. The logarithms of negative numbers, Leibniz insisted, had to exist in a domain beyond the visible, i.e., the “imaginary” (not “impossible”). However, Leibniz was unable to complete this work and it wasn’t until Gauss developed his concept of the complex domain, that the full implications of Leibniz’ conjecture were resolved.

In the intervening period, Euler, commenting on the dispute between Leibniz and Bernoulli, developed a formal demonstration that indicated Leibniz, not Bernoulli was correct concerning the logarithms of negative numbers. Out of this came Euler’s famous identity, ePi?-1 – 1 = 0, a formula that has been used to torture students and brainwash potential thinkers ever since. For Euler, this was merely a formalism that has no real meaning other than the successful manipulation of symbols according to a regular set of rules. Countless victims have been brainwashed trying to find a meaning in this formalism within the formal mathematical domain. This is not possible, because the ?-1 is not possible in the formal mathematical domain of Euler, no matter how many times he refers to it.

Nevertheless, if looked at from the standpoint of Leibniz, Huygens, and Gauss, we can remove the mysticism associated with Euler’s identity and, using Cusa’s method of transforming the finite into the infinite, bring the matter clearly into view.

In the accompanying figure, the alternating areas of blue and yellow are all unit areas. Moving to the right, equal areas correspond to the logarithms that produce increasing powers of “e”. For example, beginning at 1, (where the logarithm is 0 because no area has been swept out) moving one unit area to the right increases the length from 1 to e. Moving another unit area increases the logarithm of 1 to 2 and the length from e to e2. Halving the area between 1 and e produces the length ?e or e1/2.

When moving left from 1, the principle of equal areas is maintained, but in the opposite direction. The lengths produced by these areas are the inverses of those produced by moving to the right. For example, moving one unit area to the left produces the length 1/e. Moving two unit areas left produces 1/e2, etc.

The paradox to which Leibniz referred emerges when one tries to think how the hyperbola can produce a logarithm of a negative number. As is evident from the diagram, moving to right increases the lengths geometrically, while moving to the left decreases them. But because of the asymptotic nature of the hyperbola, the areas can never produce a length on the other side of 0.

As can be seen from the diagram, -1 is accessible, but only if the action detaches from the hyperbola and moves along the pathway around the circle. That is, to produce a logarithm of a negative number, we have to cross Kepler’s infinite boundary between the hyperbola and the circle! Half way around the circle will produce a length of -1. Dividing that action in half will, therefore, produce the action that corresponds to ?-1. Thus the logarithm of -1 can be thought of as a function of Pi and ?-1.

This matter cannot be resolved except from the standpoint of Gauss’ concept of the complex domain. Moving left and right within the domain of the hyperbola yields negative logarithms, but not the logarithms of negative numbers. Consequently, a higher concept that goes beyond simple back and forth action is required. This is exactly what Gauss specified as his complex domain.

As stated in his second treatise on biquadratic residues,: “Positive and negative numbers can be used only where the entity counted possesses an opposite, such that the unification of the two can be considered as equivalent to their dissolution. Judged precisely, this precondition is fulfilled only where relations between pairs of objects are the things counted, rather than substances (i.e. individually conceived objects). In this way we postulate that objects are ordered in some definite way into a series, for example A, B, C, D, … where the relation of A to B can be considered as identical to the relation of B to C and so forth. Here the concept of opposite consists of nothing else but interchanging the members of the relation, so that if the relation of (or transition from) A to B is taken as +1, then the relation of B to A must be represented by -1. Insofar as the series is unbounded in both directions, each real whole number represents the relation of an arbitrarily chosen member, taken as origin, to some determinate other member in the series.

“Suppose however the objects are of such a nature that they cannot be ordered in a single series, even if unbounded in both directions, but can only be ordered in a series of series, or in other words form a manifold of two dimensions; if the relation of one series to another or the transition from one series to another occurs in a similar manner as we earlier described for the transition from a member of one series to another member of the same series, then in order to measure the transition from one member of the system to another we shall require in addition to the already introduced units +1 and -1 two additional, opposite units +i and -i. Clearly we must also postulate that the unit i always signifies the transition from a given member to a determined member of the immediately adjacent series. In this manner the system will be doubly ordered into a series of series.”

In our diagram, the hyperbola is determining the action in the domain of logarithms of positive numbers, while the circle is generating action in the “imaginary” domain where the logarithms of negative numbers reside. If one mentally rotates the hyperbola perpendicular to the circle, as is its orientation within the cone, it would no longer be visible in our diagram. From this view, the hyperbola becomes, “imaginary” and the circle, “real”.

The complex domain is neither the domain of the “imaginary”, nor the “real”. It is the domain of possibility ( potential or power). As Riemann noted it is the efficient metaphor from which emerge, “a harmony and regularity that otherwise would remain hidden.”

To see this, look again at the harmony presented in the last installment. (See Figure 6, 7, 8, 9.)

When the catenary is expressed in the complex domain, the hyperbola and the circle (ellipses) are not on opposite sides of the infinite, but reside together, as a unified network of orthogonal least- action pathways within the complex domain.

If you listen carefully, you just might here, in these hidden harmonies, echos of Beethoven’s late string quartets.

Riemann for Anti-Dummies: Part 36 : Transcendental Harmonics

Riemann For Anti-Dummies Part 36

TRANSCENDENTAL HARMONIES

Discoveries indicating the existence of what Gauss would later call the complex domain began with Pythagoras and his followers in the 6th Century B.C, These discoveries, which include the ratios of musical intervals, the doubling of the line, square and cube, the five regular solids, and many others, demonstrated that universal principles expressed themselves in the shadow world of the senses by harmonic proportions. Yet, in all cases, this harmony was never complete. There was always some small discrepancy, some paradoxical dissonance, that indicated a still undiscovered principle. This is why Pythagoras called geometry “science or inquiry”, and, according to Proclus, he thought that each discovery, “sets up a platform to ascend by, and lifts the soul on high instead of allowing it to go down among sensible objects and so become subservient to the common needs of this mortal life.”

The most persistent of the dissonances recognized by the Pythagoreans were not resolved until nearly 2500 years later, when, Bernhard Riemann, in his 1851 doctoral dissertation, noted that in Gauss’ domain of complex magnitudes, “a harmony and regularity emerge that otherwise remains hidden.”

To discover these otherwise hidden harmonies, we must first take a closer look at some paradigmatic discoveries in which the dissonances arise:

Pythagoras discovered that the concordant musical intervals corresponded to the proportions, 2:1, 3:2, 4:3, if produced by a straight vibrating string. These ratios produced the intervals known as the octave, fifth and fourth, respectively. More importantly, the Pythagoreans also discovered that if these proportions are simply extended, a discrepancy emerged called the Pythagorean comma.(See Fred Haight Pedagogy.) However, ideas are conveyed by the human voice singing poetry, not vibrating strings. The comma, therefore, is not a mere deficiency. It is an indication that a higher principle exists, a principle that actually governs musical harmonies, but which cannot be derived from the manifold of vibrating strings. It can only be derived from the manifold that has come to be known as the well-tempered system of bel canto polyphony, to which many analogies can be drawn to the complex domain. (fn. 1.)

Similar harmonic proportions are expressed by the principles governing the extension of a line, square and cube. Extension of a line produces relationships that the Pythagoreans called “arithmetic”, which correspond to the musical interval of a fifth. Extension of a square produces relationships called by the Pythagoreans, “geometric”, which correspond to the Lydian musical interval. While the arithmetic and geometric are harmonic within their own individual domain, together they form a dissonance, expressed as the incommensurability between arithmetic and geometric magnitudes. That dissonance indicates, as Plato noted, that the line and square were produced by principles of different “powers”.

The extension of the cube produces a third, higher, power, that cannot be generated by the line or square. Nevertheless, this power is expressed in the lower domain of squares by two geometric means between two extremes. But, as the discoveries of, most notably, Archytus and Menaechmus, showed, the construction of the magnitudes of this third power, cannot be generated by the squares among whose shadows it dwells. This cubic power is only generated by a higher form of curvature, such as that associated with conic sections and the torus.

Plato understood that the extension of line, square and cube denoted a succession of distinct higher powers. Leibniz would later discover an even higher principle that transcended all such powers. He called this transcendental principle, “exponential” or, inversely, “logarithmic”, the significance of which will be made more clear below.

Another class of harmonic proportions investigated by Pythagoras and his followers was associated with the five regular solids and the constructability of the regular polygons. The regular solids and constructable polygons were artifacts produced by the harmonic divisions of the sphere and circle. However, these harmonic divisions are bounded. There are only five regular divisions of the sphere, and, at least as far as the Pythagoreans were concerned, the constructable polygons were limited to the triangle, square, pentagon and certain combinations of the same. (fn.2.) The boundaries confronted by the divisions of the sphere and circle express a dissonance with respect to the harmonies governing those divisions.

This general class of principles, that is those associated with the divisions of the sphere and circle also comprise a class of transcendentals called “trigonometric”.

The unity between these two classes of transcendentals exemplifies the otherwise hidden harmony to which Riemann refers in his dissertation.

The first step toward the elaboration of this unity was taken by Nicholas of Cusa, who, citing Pythagoras, recognized that all universal principles expressed themselves harmonically in the domain of the senses. But, Cusa emphasized that these harmonies could only be expressed by the transcendental magnitudes typified by the dissonances identified in the above examples. Cusa, thus presented, the paradoxical proposition that the art of science is to seek out the dissonances and discover the transcendental principle that harmonizes them.

Johannes Kepler, applying Cusa’s insight, provided the first crucial experimental demonstration that physical principles could only be known through this transcendental harmony. This begins with his discovery of the harmonic correspondence between the five regular solids and the approximate orbits of the six visible planets, the discovery of which, Kepler states, depended on Cusa’s emphasis of the dissonance between the curved (spherical) and the straight (planar). Kepler’s further discovery of the eccentricity of the planetary orbits expressed another harmony through dissonance. Unlike a circular orbit, the regular divisions of an eccentric are dependent not on the angle, but on the sine of the angle, which is transcendental to the angle. Additionally, Kepler showed that the harmonic relationships among the orbital eccentricities of all the planets are dependent, not on the simple harmonies of the vibrating string, but on the dissonances indicated by the Pythagorean comma. (See “How Gauss Determined the Orbit of Ceres”, Summer 1998 Fidelio, and earlier installments of “Riemann for Anti-Dummies”.)

Fermat’s proof that the principle of least-time, not shortest distance, governed the propagation of light, is another experimental demonstration of physical action that is dependent not on the equality of angles, but on the proportionality of the sine.

In sum, the discoveries of Kepler and Fermat demonstrate that harmonic relationships in the physical universe are, as Cusa indicated, not expressible by precisely calculable numbers, but only by transcendental quantities a polyphony of dissonances.

The Leibniz-Bernoulli collaborative investigations into the principle governing the hanging chain, provide the crucial step to Riemann’s assertion.

As detailed in other locations, Bernoulli applying the principles of Leibniz’ calculus, demonstrated that the physical principle that determined the shape of the hanging chain was expressed by a proportionality of the sines of the angles formed by the chain and the physical singularity located at the chain’s lowest point. (See figure 1.)

On the other hand, Leibniz demonstrated that this same physical principle was also expressed as an exponential function. (See figure 2.)

Thus, the catenary expresses a unifying physical principle between what had appeared to be two different classes of transcendentals: the trigonometric and exponential. That unity, as Riemann indicates, only fully emerges when seen from the standpoint of Gauss’ complex domain.

The means to discover that harmonic unity, as in a musical composition, is by inversion.

Remember that the exponential and trigonometric functions first emerged as dissonances embedded in the harmonic relationships among objects in the visible domain. Now, think of those objects as artifacts of the dissonances, instead of the dissonances as artifacts of the objects.

For example, think of the circle as an artifact of the trigonometric transcendentals, and the line, square and cube, as artifacts of the transcendental exponential function. (See animation 1 and animation 2.)

This poses the difficulty of forcing the mind, as Cusa insists, away from the simple harmonic proportions among objects of visible space, to the transcendental harmonic proportions among the principles that generate them.

If we use the principle of the catenary as a pivot, we can present, at least in an intuitive form, the harmony of which Riemann speaks. A more complete demonstration will be left to future pedagogicals and to the oral discussions that this installment will undoubtedly provoke.

As previously noted, the catenary expresses both the trigonometric and the exponential functions. Thus, the catenary as the principle of physical least-action, subsumes both the principle of constant length (circle) and constant area (hyperbolic). (See figure 4.)

To this Leibniz added a new crucial conception: the exponential is the curve that embodies the principle of self-similar change. (See figure 5.) This led Leibniz to discover a new transcendental number that he denoted by the letter “b”. (Euler later derived the same quantity from formal algebra and denoted it by the letter “e” which is used today. It is typical of today’s academic frauds that this discovery is attributed to Euler’s formalism, instead of Leibniz’ Socratic idea.)

Figure 5

We have already seen how the hyperbola is generated by the exponential functions derived from the catenary. But, the exponential also generates the circle when the circle is thought of, as it should be, as a special case of an exponential spiral. Keep in mind Kepler’s projective relationship among the conic sections. (See Riemann for Anti-Dummies Part 33.) For Kepler the circle and the hyperbola were at opposite extremes of one manifold, and as such embody a common principle of generation. But, in that projective relationship, there was a discontinuous gap, a dissonance, between the hyperbola and the circle, giving the appearance that the hyperbola was on the “other side of the infinite” from the circle. Only in the complex domain of Gauss and Riemann does that gap disappear and that common generating principle harmonically expressed.

Since both the circle and the hyperbola are generated by the common principle expressed by the exponential, the trigonometric and hyperbolic functions can be represented as complex functions. Riemann created a concept of complex functions as transformations that produce manifolds of action, which in turn produce least-action pathways within that manifold. The study of complex functions formed the basis of Riemann’s work on algebraic, hypergeometric and abelian functions, which will be elaborated in future installments. As a precondition to that deeper study, we provide the reader with an intuitive view of the “otherwise hidden harmony and regularity” that emerges there.

Figures 6, 7, 8, 9, illustrate the complex mappings of the sine cosine, hyperbolic sine and hyperbolic cosine. As can be seen, all four functions express as artifacts, not one hyperbola or circle, but a system of orthogonal hyperbolas and circles.

Figures 10 and 11, and figures 12 and 13 illustrate surfaces constructed by the complex sine, cosine, hyperbolic sine and hyperbolic cosine. In the visible domain the circle is closed and periodic, while the hyperbola is infinite. Yet, when viewed from the standpoint of the complex domain, both are periodic. The shape of the curves rising from the surface, in both cases, are catenaries!

And, this is only the beginning.

NOTES

1. The analogy between well-tempered polyphony and the complex domain is most directly seen in the late quartets of Beethoven. There the characteristic half-step boundaries between neighboring keys and modes are transformed. Just as a solid is bounded by surfaces and a surface is bounded by lines, Beethoven transforms the keys and modes from the bounded to the boundaries of a “musical solid”.

2. It was one of Gauss’ earliest discoveries of the complex domain that the constructable polygons included the 17-gon and all polygons with the prime number of sides of the form 22^n + 1.

3. For generations students have been brainwashed by the Euler’s mystical algebraic derivation of the unity between the exponential and the trigonometric. The algebraic form of the circle as the curve of constant length is x2 + y2 = 1, where x and y are the legs of a right triangle. The algebraic expression of the hyperbola is x2 – y2 = 1. When factored algebraically the circle yields, (x + y?-1)(x – y?-1), while the hyperbola yields (x + y)(x – y).

Riemann for Anti-Dummies: Part 35 : Mind as a Power Generator

Riemann For Anti-Dummies Part 35

MIND AS POWER GENERATOR

Rene Descartes (1596-1630) was, for all intents and purposes, a Bogomil. The geometry that bears his name, is brainwashing. Anyone exposed to it, unless cured, will suffer from cognitive deficiency. Symptoms include impotence and an inability to distinguish fantasy from reality.

Gottfried Leibniz, writing to Molanus, circa 1679, recognized the deleterious effects of Cartesianism, “Cartesians are not capable of discovery; they merely undertake the job of interpreting or commenting upon their master, as the Scholastics did with Aristotle. There have been many beautiful discoveries since Descartes, but, as far as I know, not one of them has come from a true Cartesian…. Descartes himself had a rather limited mind.”

Descartes’ method is impotent. It lacks power. Go back to the investigations of the Pythagoreans, Archytas, Menaechmus and Plato, on the matter of doubling the line, square and cube. These discoveries demonstrated, the relationship between objects and the principles from which they are generated. Each principle possess a characteristic power. The succession of objects– line, square and cube– are produced by a succession of higher powers (dunamis). These powers are not defined by the objects. The objects are produced by the powers. The powers cannot be known through the senses. The characteristics of the physical powers are, nevertheless, made sensible through their harmony, which only the mind has the power to grasp.

As can be seen from the solutions to doubling the cube by Archytas and Menaechmus, the harmonic relationship among these powers reflects a characteristic curvature, that, when projected onto straight lines, produces the relationships the Pythagoreans recognized as the arithmetic, geometric and sub-contrary, (or harmonic) means. The arithmetic mean is three numbers related by a common difference: c – a = b – c, or, c = 1/2 (a+b). Geometrically, it is represented by the half-way point along a line; musically it corresponds to the interval of the fifth. The geometric mean is three numbers in constant proportion: a:b::b:c. Geometrically it is represented by the middle square between two squares; musically it corresponds to the Lydian interval. The harmonic mean is the inverse of the arithmetic mean: 1/c = 1/2(1/a+1/b). It is expressed geometrically in the hyperbola and musically by the interval of the fourth. These harmonic relationships are number shadows cast by the curved onto the straight. (See Riemann for Anti-Dummies 33. EIR website.)

Riemann generalized these Greek discoveries by his notion of multiply extended magnitude. The line is an artifact of a simply-extended manifold, the square an artifact of a doubly-extended manifold, and the cube an artifact of triply-extended manifold. For Riemann, as for Pythagoras, Archytas, Menaechmus, Plato, et al., each increase of degree of extension, from “n” to “n+1”, occurs by the addition of a new principle, not a new independent “dimension”. Consequently, a square cannot be produced from a line, nor a cube from a square, because the square is generated by a different principle than the line, as the cube is generated from a different principle than the square. But, Riemann also made clear, that extension alone is insufficient to determine physical geometry. Another principle is necessary: physical curvature. (See Riemman for Anti-Dummies, Parts 28, 29, 33, 34).

In Descartes’ make-believe world, the concept of power is excised. “Any problem in geometry can easily be reduced to such terms that a knowledge of lengths of certain straight lines is sufficient for its construction,” is the opening of his treatise on analytical geometry.

As a true Bogomil, Descartes is perverse. He begins ass backward, starting with numerical relationships, stripped of their power, and pretending to generate curves, from only these numberical relationships which he wrote down in the form of an algebraic equation. This is pure fakery, as Descartes never derived any curve from these equations. All the numerical relationships had already been discovered by Apollonius, through the investigations of the relationship between curvature and power. Descartes never generated a single curve whose harmonic relationships had not already been discovered by the Greeks. Descartes’ intention was to strip the power from ideas and the idea of powers from geometry.

To illustrate this point concretely, look at Menaechmus’ solution for the problem of doubling the cube, presented in Riemann for Anti-Dummies 33. Menaechmus demonstrated that the magnitude that doubles the cube is formed by the intersection of a parabola and an hyperbola. Each curve embodies a different set of proportions that emerge when the curved is combined with the straight. For example, the hyperbola is formed by the corner of a rectangle whose sides change such that the area remains the same. The parabola is formed by the corner of a rectangle in which one side is always the square of the other. These rectangles are made up of straight lines, whose proportionality is determined by the curves. The curves posses the power to produce that proportionality, and that power is expressed in the relationship between the curve and the straight lines produced by it. In other words, only a faker or a fool would separate the curve, the straight-lines and the proportionality that produces this complex of action. As Menaechmus demonstrates, when the hyperbola and parabola are combined, a power is expressed by the resulting proportionality, which is higher than exists in either curve independently.

For Descartes, the straight lines are independent entities, created without reason. The curve and the associated powers are deviations from these straight lines. “Here it must be observed that by a2, b3, and similar expressions, I ordinarily mean only simple lines, which, however, I name squares, cubes, etc., so that I may make use of the terms employed in algebra,” he confessed. Thus, the fantasy make believe world of independent straight lines is taken as primary and the real world of physical action, is only a deviation from the fantasy world. Since, as Leibniz stated, this way of thinking is incapable of producing discoveries, the only intention of those teaching it, is to condition the students into believing the fantasy world has more power than reality. (The baby-boomer populist’s obsession that money equals economic security is a typical result of this type of education.)

To hammer this home and to prepare the ground for taking on Riemann’s physical differential geometry, look at two physical examples: the conic section orbit of a heavenly body around the sun; the catenary; and Gauss’ Geoid.

In the first case, the heavenly body is conforming to a unique curved pathway around the sun, which Kepler and Gauss demonstrated was a conic section with the sun at a common focus for all orbits. Thus, the orbits define a physical pathway, and the sun a physical origin. The straight-lines that have physical significance are the ones related to the physical action. For example, the major axis of an elliptical orbit is the line that connects the points of minimum and maximum speed, which are also the points of maximum curvature. The parameter of the orbit is the line going through the sun that is perpendicular to the major axis of the conic section. The minor axis of the elliptical orbit is the line connecting the points of minimum curvature of the orbit. These lines express the harmonic relationships of the arithmetic, geometric and harmonic means, which in turn reflect the higher powers, the “reason” why the planet’s orbit takes the shape it does. (See Appendix to “How Gauss Determined the Orbit of Ceres”, Summer 1998 Fidelio.)

Now look at the catenary. Despite Descartes’ boast that his method could solve any problem in geometry, the hanging chain proved him wrong. The catenary presents a different problem than the conic section orbits. It did not conform to any known geometrical figure, so its nature had to be discovered only from its physical characteristics. This presented a problem for Descartes because unless the nature of the curve was known, he could not determine where to put his straight lines.

Leibniz and Bernoulli demonstrated, that physical nature of the catenary is expressed by the relationship between any point on the chain, and the lowest point. That relationship is measured by the tangents to the curve at these two points. (See “Justice for the Catenary”, Schiller Institute website.) The tangent to the lowest point is always perpendicular to the pull of gravity, i.e. horizontal. The relationship of the force between any point on the catenary and this lowest point, is measured by the sines of the angles formed by the tangents to these two points, and a vertical line drawn from the lowest point. In other words, the physical action at any point on the catenary, is expressed by a “differential” relationship between the angles formed by these three lines. The horizontal tangent to the lowest point, which is perpendicular to the pull of gravity, a vertical line drawn from that point, which is along the direction of the pull of gravity, and the tangent to the point on the curve.

Leibniz and Bernoulli showed that this “differential” change does not conform to any previous known algebraic curve. It does not exist in Descartes’ world. Descartes could not determine how to construct this curve from straight lines. (Anyone indoctrinated in Descartes method will be getting very uncomfortable now.) But, obviously the chain exists in the real world. As we just observed, the only lines that are relevant are those determined, physically, by the changing relationship of the catenary to the pull of gravity and the perpendicular to the pull of gravity. This changing relationship is not determined by Cartesian geometry. It is determined by the physical curvature of the pull of gravity. Leibniz and Bernoulli demonstrated, that this relationship is expressed by the exponential and hyperbolic functions, both of which are expressions of a succession of higher powers, and as such, undiscoverable by the Cartesian method. (See Riemann for Anti-Dummies 33. EIR website.)

Gauss’ Geoid presents a still different problem. In the previous two examples, the “differential” of action was along a pathway determined by the principle of universal gravitation. In these cases, the “differential” could be determined with respect to a doubly-extended magnitude. (The major axis and parameter for the orbit and the pull of gravity and its perpendicular for the catenary.) In determining the shape of the Earth, Gauss confronted the addition of a new principle. Instead of measuring along a pathway in a doubly-extended surface, he was measuring changes of the surface itself. For pedagogical purposes, think of measuring a triangle on a perfect sphere. How does the shape of that triangle change as the area of the triangle increases? Compare this with measuring a triangle on an irregular surface, such as a watermelon. One the sphere, the sides of the triangles change because they are circles in all directions. However, on a watermelon, the sides of the triangle change according to a different principle depending on the direction. To measure this type of change, Gauss invented a new type of complex differential, which will be developed more fully in future pedagogicals.

To summarize the epistemological issues raised in this pedagogical, we quote Leibniz disputing Descartes theory of motion:

“There was a time when I believed that all phenomena of motion could be explained on purely geometrical principles, assuming no metaphysical propositions…But, through a more profound meditation, I discovered that this is impossible, and I learned a truth higher than all mechanics, namely that everything in nature can indeed be explained mechanically, but that th e principles of mechanics themselves depend on metaphysical and, in a sense moral principles, that is, on the contemplation of the most perfectly effectual efficient and final cause, namely, God…

“…I discovered that this, so to speak, inertia of bodies cannot be deduced from the initially assumed notion of matter and motion, where matter is understood as that which is extended or fills space, and motion is understood as change of space or place. But rather, over and above that which is deduced from extension and its variation or modification alone, we must add and recognize in bodies certain notions or forms that are immaterial, so to speak, or independent of extension, which you can call powers, by means of which speed is adjusted to magnitude. These powers consist not in motion, indeed, not in conatus or the beginning of motion, but in the cause or in that intrinsic reason for motion, which is the law required for continuing. And investigators have erred insofar as they considered motion, but not motive power or the reason for motion, which even if derived from God, author and governor of things, must not be understood as being n God himself, but must be understood as having been produced and conserved by him in things. From this we shall also show that it is not the same quantity of motion (which misleads many), but the same powers that are conserved in the world.”

Riemann for Anti-Dummies: Part 34 : Power and Curvature

Riemann for Anti-Dummies Part 34

POWER AND CURVATURE

In his 1854 habilitation lecture, Bernhard Riemann spoke of the twofold task involved in lifting more than 2,000 years of darkness that had settled on science:

“From Euclid to Legendre, to name the most renowned of modern writers on geometry, this darkness has been lifted neither by the mathematicians nor by the philosophers who have labored upon it. The reason of this lay perhaps in the fact that the general concept of multiply extended magnitudes, in which spatial magnitudes are comprehended, has not been elaborated at all. Accordingly, I have proposed to myself at first the problem of constructing the concept of a multiply extended magnitude out of general notions of quantity. From this it will result that a multiply extended magnitude is susceptible of various metric relations and that space accordingly constitutes only a particular case of a triply-extended magnitude. A necessary sequel of this is that the propositions of geometry are not derivable from general concepts of quantity, but those properties by which space is distinguished from other conceivable triply-extended magnitudes can be gathered only by experience. There arises from this the problem of searching out the simplest facts by which the metric relations of space can be determined, a problem which in the nature of things is not quite definite; for several systems of simple facts can be stated which would suffice for determining the metric relations of space; the most important for present purposes is that laid down for foundations by Euclid. These facts are, like all facts, not necessary but of a merely empirical certainty; they are hypotheses….”

To grasp the significance of Riemann’s “Plan of Investigation,” it must be recognized that the 2,000 years of darkness of which he spoke, was, like the foundations of Euclidean geometry, not necessary. The Romantic cult-belief that the definitions, axioms, and postulates of Euclid, were the {a priori}, fixed, immutable and necessary condition of the universe, never had any basis in truth. It was a false doctrine imposed by an imperial system, which required the widespread acceptance of the belief that the universe was ruled by forces beyond human comprehension and control, and that these forces could only be administered by an oligarchical authority. The edicts of this oligarchy, like the definitions, axioms, and postulates of Euclidean geometry, were laid down as given, not requiring, nor susceptible of, proof. They were simply, “the way things are.”

This view was expressed succinctly by the hoaxster, Claudius Ptolemy, the hatchet-man who imposed the knowingly false, fixed, geocentric conception of the solar system. Ptolemy, agreeing with Aristotle, justified his attack on Aristarchus’ provably true heliocentric conception, as a necessary consequence of his view of Man. In the introduction to his {Almagast}, Ptolemy stated that knowledge of both God and the physical universe was impossible. The only knowledge accessible to man was, what Ptolemy called “mathematical,” that is, knowledge which follows logically from a given set of axioms, definitions, and postulates. Those axioms, definitions and postulates, themselves can not be proven. As such, their authority resides not in demonstrable truths, but in the arbitrary power of whoever decrees their primacy. The evil lies not with the axioms, postulates, and definitions themselves, but in the acceptance of the method that knowledge can be derived only from them.

The popular acceptance of the darkness ushered in by the dominance of this Aristotelean method was a tragic degeneration from a higher concept of man and the universe developed in Classical Greece from Pythagoras until the murder of Archimedes. Euclid’s {Elements}, in a strange way, demonstrate this themselves. Read in their customary order, the {Elements} proceed from the definitions of point, line, surface, and solid, as objects of, respectively, 0, 1, 2, and 3 “dimensions,” and certain postulates about the unlimitedness of these objects. From there, a set of theorems is developed that elaborate the possible actions in a universe that conforms to the restrictions contained in the opening definitions, axioms, and postulates.

Yet read backwards, Euclid’s {Elements} begin to reveal a completely different comprehension of the universe. The {Elements} end where they should begin–with the construction of the five regular (Platonic) solids from the characteristic of spherical action. This investigation leads to the discovery of magnitudes of different powers, as exhibited in the problem of doubling the line, square, and cube. The relationships among these powers, give rise to the proportions called the arithmetic, geometric, and harmonic means, and to the prime numbers and the relationships among them. Only then do the investigations concern the reflection of these relationships in a plane. Only at the end, should we arrive at the point, line, surface, and solid. Seen in this way, these objects are concepts arising from a higher principle–the action that produced the five regular solids from a sphere–not as objects created by arbitrary decree from below, in the form of axioms, definitions, and postulates.

(It is from this standpoint that Kepler begins his {Harmony of the World} with a strong denunciation of Petrus Ramus, the leading Aristotelean of the day, who sought to ban books 10 through 13 of Euclid.)

This principle is similarly demonstrated by the Pythagorean/Platonic investigations of doubling the line, square, and cube. As discussed in previous pedagogicals, each object is generated by magnitudes of successively higher powers. The relationship among these higher powers is reflected by the arithmetic and geometric proportions. Initially, it appears that each power is associated simply with an increase in extension. For example, the magnitude that doubles the square is incommensurable with the magnitude that doubles the line, but it is produced from within the square. Yet, when the problem of doubling the cube is considered, the sought-after magnitude is not generated anywhere in the cube. Both the constructions of Archytus and Menaechmeus demonstrate, that the magnitude that has the power to double the cube is produced by the higher form of action represented by the cone, torus, and cylinder. While that action has a causal effect on the generation of cube, it is not produced anywhere in the cube. In other words, it is not produced by an increase in extension from two to three “dimensions.”

Another principle is involved. As emphasized in last week’s pedagogical discussion, the principle that generates the magnitude that doubles the cube, is expressed in a change of “curvature.”

As Riemann stated in his habilitation paper, the determination of extension is only the first step:

“Now that the concept of an n-fold extended manifold has been constructed and its essential mark has been found to be this, that the determination of position therein can be referred to n determinations of magnitude, there follows as second of the problems proposed above, an investigation into the relations of measure that such a manifold is susceptible of, also, into the conditions which suffice for determining these metric relations.”

To illustrate this pedagogically, perform the following experiment. Stand in the corner of a room and mark one point on the ceiling above your head, a second point on the wall directly to your right, and a third point on the other wall directly to your left. Now, in your mind connect these three points. If you point to these points in succession, the motion of your arm will define three right angles, implying that these three points all lie on the surface of a sphere. However, if you connect these points, in your mind, with straight lines, the points now lie on a flat surface, forming the triangular face of an octahedron. On the other hand, if you connect the three points to one another by hanging strings between them, the surface thus formed will be bounded by catenaries, and thus be negatively curved. These three points form three different triangles, which in all three cases, are doubly-extended magnitudes. Yet, each is very different from the other. The difference lies not in the degree of extension, but in the curvature of the surface on which the triangle lies. Thus, the lines that form the sides of these triangles, are defined by the nature of the surface in which they exist. The Euclidean definition of a line as “breadthless length,” cannot distinguish the side of the spherical triangle from the flat or negatively curved one; nor can the Euclidean definition of surface as, “that which has length and breadth only,” distinguish the three triangles from one another.

The curvature of these three surfaces can be measured by the sum of the angles of the triangles formed on each. On the spherical triangle, the sum of the angles is greater than 180 degrees. On the flat one, the sum of the angles is exactly 180 degrees. On the “catenary” triangle, the sum of the angles is less than 180 degrees.

Now, think, as Gauss and Riemann did, of a manifold that encompasses all three curvatures. Begin first with a positively curved surface such as a sphere. Here the sum of the angles of a triangle is always greater than 180 degrees. The larger the triangle, the greater the sum, until a maximum is reached when the triangle covers the whole sphere. As these triangles become smaller, the sum of the angles approaches, but never reaches 180 degrees, for when the sum of the angles reaches 180 degrees, the surface becomes flat. On a negatively curved surface, just the opposite occurs. As the triangle becomes smaller, the sum of the angles of a triangle gets larger, approaching, but never reaching 180 degrees.

These three surfaces form a manifold of action, in which the flat plane of Euclid is only the momentary transition between a negatively and a positively curved surface.

Gauss saw in this the possibility of a physical determination of geometry.

“It is easy to prove, that if Euclid’s geometry is not true, there are no similar figures. The angles of an equal-sided triangle, vary according to the magnitude of the sides, which I do not at all find absurd. It is thus, that angles are a function of the sides and the sides are functions of the angles, and at the same time, a constant line occurs naturally in such a function. It appears something of a paradox, that a constant line could possibly exist, so to speak, {a priori}; but, I find in it nothing contradictory. It were even desirable, that Euclid’s Geometry were not true, because then we would have, {a priori}, a universal measurement, for example, one could use for a unit of space [{Raumeinheit}], the side of an equilateral triangle, whose angle is 59 degrees, 59 minutes, 59.99999… seconds.”

Riemann for Anti-Dummies: Part 33 : Hyperbolic Functions – A Fugue Across 25 Centuries

Riemann for Anti-Dummies Part 33

HYPERBOLIC FUNCTIONS – A FUGUE ACROSS 25 CENTURIES

When the Delians, circa 370 B.C., suffering the ravages of a plague, were directed by an oracle to increase the size of their temple’s altar, Plato admonished them to disregard all magical interpretations of the oracle’s demand and concentrate on solving the problem of doubling the cube. This is one of the earliest accounts of the significance of pedagogical, or spiritual, exercises for economics.

Some crises, such as the one currently facing humanity, require a degree of concentration on paradoxes that outlasts one human lifetime. Fortunately, mankind is endowed with what LaRouche has called, “super-genes,” which provide the individual the capacity for higher powers of concentration, by bringing the efforts of generations past into the present. Exemplary is the case of Bernhard Riemann’s 1854 habilitation lecture, On the Hypotheses that Underlie the Foundations of Geometry, in which Riemann speaks of a darkness that had shrouded human thought from Euclid to Legendre. After more than 2,000 thousand years of concentration on the matter, Riemann, standing on the shoulders of his teacher, Carl F. Gauss, lifted that darkness, by developing what he called, “a general concept of multiply-extended magnitude.”

Riemann’s concept extended the breakthroughs already put forward by Gauss, beginning with his 1799 dissertation on the fundamental theorem of algebra. Like its predecessor, it is a devastating refutation of the “ivory tower” methods of Euler, Lagrange, et al. that dominate the thinking of most of the population today, just as it dominated the minds of the Delians and the other unfortunate Greeks of Plato’s time. Recognizing that all problems of society were ultimately subjective, Plato prescribed (in The Republic) that mastery of pedagogical exercises, (in the domain of music, geometry, arithmetic, and astronomy) be a prerequisite for political leadership. Only if leaders developed the capacity to free themselves, and then others, from this wrong-headedness, could crises, like the one facing us (or that which faced the Delians), be vanquished.

These exercises accustom the mind to shift its attention from the shadows of sense perception, to the discovery of knowable, but unseen truths, that are reflected to us as paradoxes in the domain of the senses. The process is never-ending. With each new discovery, new paradoxes are brought to the surface, which provoke still further discoveries, producing an ever greater concentration of the requisite quality of mind that produced the discovery in the first place.

Doubling of the Line, Square, and Cube

Such is the context for concentrating on the 2,500-year investigation of the paradoxes initially posed by the problem of doubling the line, square, and cube. These objects appear, visually, to be similar. The square is made from lines, while the cube is made from squares. Yet, when subjected to an action, such as doubling, it becomes evident that while these objects appear visibly similar, their principle of generation is vastly different.

The Pythagoreans, who learned from the Egyptians, reportedly, were the first Greeks to investigate this paradox. Recognizing that these visibly similar, but knowably different, objects were all contained in one universe, they sought a unifying principle that underlay the generation of all three. That unifying principle could not be directly observed, but its existence could be known, through its expression, as a paradox, lurking among the shadows that were seen.

Nearly 80 years before Plato’s rebuke of the Delians, Hippocrates of Chios offered an insight based on the Pythagorean principle of the connection among music, arithmetic, and geometry. The Pythagoreans had recognized relationships among musical intervals, which they called: the arithmetic and the geometric. The arithmetic mean is found when three numbers are related by a common difference: b – a = c – b. For example, 3 is the arithmetic mean between 1 and 5. (see Figure 1a).

The geometric mean is when three numbers are in constant proportion, a:b::b:c. For example, 2:4::4:8. (see Figure 1b ).

Hippocrates recognized that the arithmetic relationship is expressed by the intervals formed when lines are added, and that the geometric is expressed by the intervals when squares, or more generally, areas, are added. The formation of solid figures, being of a still higher power, did not correspond directly to any of these musical relationships. Nevertheless, the shadow cast by the doubling of the cube, expressed a relationship that corresponded to finding two geometric means between two extremes (see Figure 1c).

Plato, in the Timaeus, explains the significance of Hippocrates’ insight:

“Now that which is created is of necessity corporeal, and also visible and tangible…. But it is not possible that two things alone be joined without a third; for in between there must needs be some bond joining the two…. Now if the body of the All had had to come into being as a plane surface, having no depth, one mean would have sufficed to bind together both itself and its fellow-terms; but now it is otherwise, for it behooved it to be solid in shape, and what brings solids into harmony is never one mean, but always two.”

In the Epinomis, Plato says of the investigations of the arithmetic and geometric means, “a divine and marvelous thing it is to those who contemplate it and reflect how the whole of nature is impressed with species and kind according to each proportion as power…. To the man who pursues his studies in the proper way, all geometric constructions, all systems of numbers, all duly constituted melodic progressions, the single ordered scheme of all celestial revolutions, should disclose themselves, and disclose themselves they will, if, as I say, a man pursues his studies aright with his mind’s eye fixed on their single end. As such a man reflects, he will receive the revelation of a single bond of natural interconnection between all these problems. If such matters are handled in any other spirit, a man, as I am saying, will need to invoke his luck. We may rest assured that without these qualifications the happy will not make their appearance in any society; this is the method, this the pabulum, these the studies demanded; hard or easy, this is the road we must tread.”

While the initial reported reaction to Hippocrates was that he had turned one impossible puzzle into another, others saw his insight as a flank. If the construction of two means between two extremes could be carried out among the shadows, the result could be applied to double the cube. Plato’s collaborator, Archytas of Tarentum, supplied a solution by his famous construction involving a cylinder, torus, and cone. (See Figure) This demonstrated that the required construction could only be carried out, not in the flat domain of the shadows, but in the higher domain of the curved surfaces. Archytas’ result is consistent with the discovery of the Pythagoreans, Theatetus, and Plato, of the construction of the five regular solids from the sphere.

Menaechmus’ Discovery

Plato’s student, Menaechmus, supplied a further discovery, by demonstrating that curves generated from cones possessed the power to produce two means between two extremes. As the accompanying diagrams illustrate, the parabola possesses the characteristic of one mean between two extremes, while the hyperbola embraces two (see Figures 2a and Figure 2b, and Animation 1a and Animation 1b).

Menaechmus showed that the intersection of an hyperbola and a parabola produces the result of placing two means between two extremes (Figure 3).

Embedded in the discoveries of Archytas and Menaechmus was a principle that would not fully blossom until 2,200 years later, with the discoveries of Riemann and Gauss. Archytas’ solution depended on a characteristic possessed by the curve formed by the intersection of the cylinder and torus. This curve could not be drawn on a flat plane, because it curved in two directions. Gauss would later define this characteristic as “negative” curvature.(Figure 4).

However, Menaechmus’ construction using a parabola and hyperbola, is carried out entirely in the flat domain of the shadows. Nonetheless, for reasons that would not become apparent until Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz in the 17th Century, Menaechmus’ solution worked because it contained this same principle of negative curvature as did Archytas’.

Because of the lack of extant original writings, it is difficult to know how conscious these ancient Greek investigators were of the principle which Gauss would call negative curvature. What is known, is that these Greeks knew that the principle that determined action in the physical universe, was a higher principle than that which dominated the flat world of areas. The principles governing solid objects, thus, depended on curves, generated by a higher type of action in space, which, when projected onto the lower domain of a plane, exhibited the capacity of putting two means between two extremes. These curves combined the arithmetic and the geometric into a One. When this principle was applied in the higher domain of solid objects, it produced the experimentally validatable result.

This demonstrates, as Plato makes clear, not simply a principle governing the physical realm, but the multiply-connected relationship between the spiritual and the material dimensions of the universe; hence the appropriateness of “pedagogical,” or “spiritual exercises.”

Kepler’s Study of Conic Sections

The next significant step was accomplished by Johannes Kepler, who established modern physical science as an extension of these ancient Greek discoveries as those discoveries were re-discovered by Nicolaus of Cusa, Luca Pacioli, and Leonardo da Vinci. Kepler, citing Cusa, whom he called “divine,” placed particular importance on the difference between the curved (geometric) and the straight (arithmetic).

“But after all, why were the distinctions between curved and straight, and the nobility of a curve, among God’s intentions when he displayed the universe? Why indeed? Unless because by a most perfect Creator it was absolutely necessary that a most beautiful work should be produced,” Kepler wrote in the Mysterium Cosmographicum.

As part of his astronomical research, Kepler mastered the compilation of Greek discoveries on these higher curves contained in Apollonius’ {Conics.} As a result of his investigation of refraction of light, Kepler reports a revolutionary new concept of conic sections. For the first time, Kepler considered the conic sections as one projective manifold:

“[T]here exists among these lines the following order by reason of their properties: It passes from the straight line through an infinity of hyperbolas to the parabola, and thence through an infinity of ellipses to the circle. Thus the parabola has on one side two things infinite in nature, the hyperbola and the straight line, the ellipse and the circle. For it is also infinite, but assumes a limitation from the other side…. Therefore, the opposite limits are the circle and the straight line: The former is pure curvedness, the latter pure straightness. The hyperbola, parabola, and the ellipse are placed in between, and participate in the straight and the curved, the parabola equally, the hyperbola in more of the straightness, and the ellipse in more of the curvedness.” (See Figure 5 and Animation 2.)

Animation 2

Of significance for this discussion is the discontinuity revealed by this projection between the parabola and the hyperbola. The hyperbola stands on the other side of the infinite, so to speak, from the ellipse and the circle, while the parabola has one side toward the infinite and the other toward the finite.

From Fermat to Gauss

The significance of this infinite boundary begins to become clear from the standpoint of Pierre de Fermat’s complete re-working of Apollonius’ Conics and the subsequent development of the calculus by Leibniz and Jean Bernoulli, with a crucial contribution supplied by Christian Huyghens.

Huyghens recognized that the curved and the straight expressed themselves in the hyperbola differently than in the other conic sections. His insight was based on the same principle recognized by Menaechmus, that the hyperbola, when projected onto a plane, was formed by a series of rectangles whose area was always equal. As one of the sides of each rectangle got longer, the other side got inversely smaller. Huyghens focused his attention on the area bounded by the hyperbola and the asymptote, which is the area formed by an ever-changing rectangle whose area is always the same (Figure 6). Areas between the hyperbola and the asymptote, formed by rectangles whose sides are in proportion, are equal. Consequently, as the diagram illustrates, those sections of the hyperbola, formed as the distance along the asymptote from the center increases geometrically, are equal. Thus, as the areas increase arithmetically, the lengths along the asymptote increase geometrically. Don’t miss the irony of this inversion: In the hyperbola, the (geometric) areas grow arithmetically, while the (arithmetic) lengths grow geometrically!

As has been presented in previous installments of this series, this combined relationship of the arithmetic with the geometric was discovered by Leibniz to be expressed by the physical principle of the catenary. Leibniz demonstrated that the catenary was formed by a curve, which he called “logarithmic,” today known as the “exponential.” This curve is formed such that the horizontal change is arithmetic, while the vertical change is geometric. The catenary, Leibniz demonstrated, is the arithmetic mean between two such “logarithmic” curves (Figure 7).

From here we are led directly into the discovery of Gauss and Riemann through Leibniz’ and Bernoulli’s other catenary-related discovery: The relationship of the catenary to the hyperbola(1). This relationship is formed from Huyghens’ discovery. The equal hyperbolic areas define certain points along the hyperbola, that are “projected” onto the axis of the hyperbola, by perpendicular lines drawn from axis to those points. These projections produce lengths along the axis, that are the same lengths that, as Leibniz showed, produced the catenary! (See Figure 8a, Figure 8b, Figure 8c and Figure 8d.)

The implications of this discovery become even more clear when viewed from the standpoint of Gauss’ investigation of curved surfaces that arose out of his earlier work on the fundamental theorem of algebra, geodesy, astronomy, and biquadratic residues. To complete this discussion, focus on Gauss’ extension of the investigations of curves, into the investigation of the surfaces which contain them. Surfaces that contained curves with the characteristics of the hyperbola or catenary, Gauss called “negatively” curved, while surfaces that were formed by curves with the characteristics of circles and ellipses, he called “positively” curved(2). (See Figures 9.)

Now think back over this 2,500-year fugue. The principle underlying the constructions of Archytas and Menaechmus; the discontinuity expressed by the infinite boundary between the hyperbola and parabola; the inversion of the geometric and arithmetic in the hyperbola: From Gauss’ perspective, these all reflect a transformation between negative and positive curvature.

Thus, to investigate action in the physical universe, it is necessary to extend the inquiry from simple extension to curvature and from simple curves to the surfaces that contain them. This, as will be developed in future installments, can only be done from the standpoint of Gauss and Riemann’s complex domain.

NOTES

1. It should be noted that this discovery has been the victim of such a widespread pogrom initiated by Euler, Lagrange, and carried into the 20th Century by Felix Klein et al., that the mere discussion of it with anyone exposed to an academic mathematics education, is likely to provoke severe outbreaks of anxiety.

2. The reason for the names “negative” and “positive” will be discussed in a future installment.

Riemann for Anti-Dummies: Part 32 : The Beginnings of Differential Geometry

Riemann for Anti-Dummies Part 32

THE BEGINNINGS OF DIFFERENTIAL GEOMETRY

Fifty-two years after Gauss’ 1799 doctoral dissertation on the fundamental theorem of algebra, his student, Bernhard Riemann, submitted, to Gauss, an equally revolutionary doctoral dissertation that took Gauss’ initial discovery into a new, higher, domain. Riemann’s thesis, “Foundations for a general theory of functions of a single variable complex magnitude”, built on the foundations of Gauss’ own work, established a complete generalization of the principles of physical differential geometry that was set into motion by Kepler nearly 250 years earlier.

It is beneficial, and perhaps essential, as a preliminary to a more detailed discussion of Riemann’s work itself, to review three exemplary discoveries of physical principles, that taken together, trace the historical development of the ideas leading into Riemann’s work: Kepler’s principles of planetary motion; the Leibniz-Bernoulli discovery of the principle of the catenary; and Gauss’ own work in geodesy. All three, while seemingly diverse, are in fact intimately connected. They all deal, in one way or another, with investigations into the nature of universal gravitation, and, taken together, they comprise a succession of concepts of increasing generality and power.

Begin first with Kepler. Taken in its entirety, from the Mysterium Cosmographicum to the Harmonice Mundi, Kepler’s work demonstrates that the action governing any planet at any moment is a function of the principle that organizes the solar system as a whole; the principle of universal gravitation. Kepler discovered that this principle has an harmonic characteristic, which determines that the planetary orbits are elliptical, not circular. The unique shape of each individual elliptical orbit is determined, not by each planet alone, nor by the pair-wise interaction of that planet with the Sun, but by the harmonic relationship among the maximum and minimum speeds of all the planets. In other words, the action of the planet at any moment is determined by these extremes, between which, the planet’s orbit “hangs”. The magnitudes of these “hanging points”, are not arbitrary, but when taken all together, conform, approximately, to the harmonic ordering of the musical scale.

The eccentricity of the planetary orbits posed a challenge to Kepler because he had no mathematical means to determine the exact position, direction and velocity of each planet at every moment, so he demanded the invention of a new mathematics. Kepler prescribed that such a mathematics must be able to determine how the harmonic principle that determines the planet’s extremes, is expressed, throughout the entire orbit, and he took the first steps toward developing that mathematics. (See Riemann for Anti-Dummies Parts 1-6)

Responding to Kepler’s demand, Leibniz and his collaborator, Johann Bernoulli developed the calculus, the most general expression of which is demonstrated by their joint effort on the catenary. At first glance, the catenary appears similar, in principle, to a planetary orbit, in that the shape of the curve seems to be determined by the position of the points from which chain hangs. As the position of these “hanging points” changes, the chain re-orients itself, so that its overall shape is maintained. In this respect, the relationship of these hanging points to all the other points on the catenary, initially seems analogous to the relationship between the extreme speeds of a planet to the entire orbit. But, as Bernoulli showed in his book on the integral calculus, all points on the catenary, except the lowest point, are, at all times, hanging points. (The reader should review Riemann for Anti-Dummies Parts 10 “Justice for the Catenary”, and chapter 4 of “How Gauss Determined the Orbit of Ceres”, to perform the experiments indicated therein.(fn. 1.)) This is, in fact, an inversion of the principle expressed in Keplerian orbits. In the case of the planet, the orbit, “hangs” between its two extremes. For the catenary, the extreme, that is the lowest point, is the one point that does no hanging. (In Cusa’s terms it is the point that is simultaneously motion and no-motion.) Applying Leibniz’ calculus, Bernoulli demonstrated how the catenary is “unfolded” from this lowest point. (fn. 2.)

Leibniz, in turn, demonstrated that this physical principle also reflected the characteristic exhibited by the logarithmic (exponential) function. (See Leibniz paper on catenary.) Thus, the hanging chain is characterized by the same transcendental principle that subsumes the generation of the so-called algebraic powers, and which is exhibited in other physical processes such as biological growth and the musical scale, as well. Consequently, the characteristics of the logarithmic (exponential) function, is an expression of a physical principle, not a mathematical one.

Now, compare the above described examples with Gauss’ discovery of the Geoid. From 1818 to 1832 Gauss carried out a geodetic survey of the Kingdom of Hannover. This involved determining the physical distances along the surface of the Earth by laying out triangles and measuring the angles formed by the “line of sight” sides. The paradox Gauss confronted was that the relationship between the lengths of the sides of the triangles and the angles, is a function of the shape of the Earth. (fn.3.) However, the shape of the Earth could not be known in advance of the measurements. The problem was further complicated by the fact that all the measurements were taken with respect to the direction of the pull of gravity, as determined by the direction of a hanging plumb bob. Like the relationship between the angles of a triangle and the lengths of the sides, the direction of the pull of gravity depends on the shape of the Earth. For example, if the Earth were spherical, the plumb bob would always point toward the center of the Earth. If the Earth were ellipsoidal, the plumb bob would point to different places, depending on where on the ellipsoid the measurement was being taken. Gauss showed that the problem was even more complicated, because the Earth’s shape was very irregular. (See Riemann for Anti-Dummies Part 17.)

Here Gauss was confronted with exactly the same type of problem as Kepler and Leibniz before him. Existing mathematics could not measure such an irregular shape. All previous approaches began with an a priori assumption of the shape of the Earth, one that conformed to existing mathematical knowledge. (This brings to mind Gallileo’s foolish insistence that the catenary was a parabola because that was the shape in the mathematical textbooks which looked most like a catenary. The chain, however, did not read Gallileo’s preferred texts.) Gauss abandoned all such attempts to fit the Earth into an assumed shape, declaring that the geometrical shape of the Earth is that shape that is everywhere perpendicular to the pull of gravity. In other words, instead of assuming an imaginary shape, and measuring the real Earth as a deviation from the imaginary one, Gauss rejected the fantasy world altogether. (Something more and more people should want to do these days as the global monetary systems disintegrates.) The physically determined shape that Gauss measured has since become known as the Geoid.

While the Geoid is an irregular surface, its irregularity is “tuned” so to speak by the motion of the Earth on its axis. Like the planetary orbit, or the hanging chain, that motion determines the positions of two, “hanging points”, specifically the north and south pole, from which the Geoid hangs.

However, since the Geoid is a surface, it has a different relationship to its poles, than the planetary orbit to its extremes, or the catenary to the lowest point. The latter two cases express the relationship between singularities and action on a curve. The former expresses the relationship between singularities and action on a surface, from which the action along the curves is derived.

The problem Gauss confronted was that since the physical triangles he measured on the surface of the Geoid were irregular, how could the lengths of the sides be determined from the angles, without first knowing the relationship between the lengths and the angles, i.e., the shape of the surface? To solve the problem, Gauss recognized that since all his measurements were angles, he could free himself from having to assume the Earth’s shape before he could determine his measurements, if he could project these angles from one surface to another, for example, from the geoid, to an ellipsoid, to a sphere and back again. Like Kepler and Leibniz, Gauss could not do this within the existing mathematics. So he invented a new one.

Gauss described the beginnings of this new mathematics in several locations, most notably his 1822 memoir on the subject of conformal mapping, that was awarded a prize from the Royal Society of Sciences of Copenhagen. Riemann relied heavily on this paper for the foundations of his own doctoral dissertation.

Conformal mapping is a term, invented by Gauss, to refer to transformations from one surface to another in which the angles between any curves on that surfaces are preserved. In his memoir, Gauss described conformal mapping as a transformation where, “the lengths of all indefinitely short lines extending from a point in the second surface and contained therein shall be proportional to the lengths of the corresponding lines in the first surface, and secondly, that every angle made between these intersecting lines in the first surface shall be equal to the angle between the corresponding lines in the second surface.”

To get an idea of what this means, perform the following experiment. Take a clear plastic hemisphere and draw a spherical triangle on it with heavy black lines. Go into a dark room and, using a flashlight, project the triangle onto the wall. If you hold the flashlight at the center of the hemisphere, the curved lines of the spherical triangle will be transformed into straight lines. If you then move the flashlight from the center of the hemisphere to a pole, the projected straight lines will become curved again, and the angles between them will be equal to the angles between the sides of the original triangle on the hemisphere.

To discover experimentally the difference between these two projections, tape cardboard circles of differing sizes onto the plastic hemisphere. (The circles should vary from quite large to quite small.) Now perform the same projection with the flashlight as before. When the flashlight is at the center of the hemisphere, these circles project to ellipses. When the flashlight is at the pole of the hemisphere, the circles become more circular, with the smaller circles become more circular than the larger ones. In the first case, the transformation of the circles into ellipses indicates that the proportion by which figures are transformed changes depending on the direction of the transformation with respect to the poles. The second case shows that the transformations are proportional in all directions.

Thus, the conformal mapping of one surface to another involves a change in rotation and direction. Having done the work on Gauss’ fundamental theorem of algebra, you should be able to recognize, as Gauss did, that this type of change could only be represented in the complex domain, which is where we will begin next time.

FOOTNOTES

1. Any two points on opposite sides of the lowest point hold up the weight of the chain hanging between them. The force required to hold up this weight is proportional to the sines of the angles made by the tangents to the catenary at this point, and a vertical line rising from the point at which the tangents intersect.

2. The reader is urged to preform the experiment described in the indicated NF article. Take a string and tie a weight in the middle of it. Hold the ends of the string in each hand and let the weight hang between them. As you move your hands apart, the tension you feel on your hands will increase. If you begin with your hands close together, the tension is relatively small. As you pull your hands apart, the tension increases, slowly at first, but the rate of increase in the tension grows, the farther apart your hands are to one another. Now try to move your hands apart, while the string slides between your fingers, so that the string on one side remains horizontal. The other hand will move in the shape of the catenary.

3. The reader can grasp this by comparing triangles drawn on a piece of paper, a sphere and an irregular shaped surface, such as a watermelon.

Riemann for Anti-Dummies: Part 31 : The Circle’s Orbital Period

Riemann for Anti-Dummies Part 31

THE CIRCLE’S ORBITAL PERIOD

Most will find what follows very challenging, but anyone who makes the effort to work it through will be richly rewarded, as the insights gained have deep implications for survival of civilization.)

If we look at the known cases of constructable polygons, the triangle, square and pentagon, each is constructable by a series of nested steps, in which a “knowable” magnitude is constructed, and then from that magnitude, another “knowable” magnitude is constructed, until the side of the polygon is found. For example, the triangle is constructed by first constructing the hexagon from the radius of the circle. Then the side of the triangle is constructed from the side of the hexagon. The square is constructed from one diameter and a second diameter is constructed perpendicular to it. The pentagon is constructed by first constructing the golden mean, and then the side of the pentagon is derived from the golden mean.

In each of the above examples, each magnitude in the chain is constructed from the its predecessor by simple circular action. Consequently, such magnitudes are commensurate with the type of magnitudes associated with doubling of the square, i.e. second degree magnitudes, which are generated by simple circular action. As distinguished from third degree magnitudes that are associated with doubling the cube, which as was seen in the construction of Archytus, require the complex action of rotation and extension.

Therefore, those polygons, whose constructions could be reduced to a nested chain of second degree magnitudes are, in principle, constructable. All others are not.

The crucial insight of Gauss was to recognize that each polygon (“planetary system”) could be constructed as a chain of “orbital periods” and “sub-periods”. The character of the magnitudes associated with these periods and sub-periods, is determined by the number-theoretic characteristics of the prime number, or more specifically, the prime number minus 1.

Herein lies the “profound connection” between the generation of transcendental magnitudes and higher Arithmetic. The arithmetical characteristics determine the geometry, while the geometry, in turn determines the arithmetical characteristics. Unlike formalists such as Euler, Lagrange and D’Alembert, Gauss saw no distinction between the geometrical and the arithmetical characteristics. The same physical principle that governed the circle, ruled number. What the circle concealed, number revealed. One need only be able, as Plato said, “to see the nature of number with the mind only.” (Remember that the Greek word from which “arithmetic” is derived has the same root as the Greek word, “harmonia”.)

For Gauss, the circle is not simply an object in visible space, but rather an artifact of an action in the complex domain. Successive divisions of the circle reflect a succession of different types of actions corresponding to the hierarchy of powers. The vertices of an “n” sided regular polygon are the “n” roots of 1. Inversely, as was shown last week, these vertices can be generated as a succession of powers.

Ironically, the principles of this so-called “imaginary” domain determine what is possible in the visible domain. Gauss showed that the deeper principle of their generation becomes known under examination of, what he called the “residues of powers” in his “Disquisitiones Arithmeticae”.

Each prime number modulus has a characteristic period of residues with respect to a series of powers. For example, the modulus 5 produces the period of residues {1, 2, 4, 3, 1, 2, 4, 3, 1, 2, 4, 3,etc.}, with respect to the powers of 2, and the period of residues {1, 3, 4, 2, 1, 3, 4, 2, 1, 3, 4, 2, etc, }, with respect to the powers of 3. (See Riemann for Anti-Dummies Parts 20-23.)

(Since the powers of 2 and 3 yield complete, albeit different, periods, they are called “primitive roots” of 5. Compare this result to the periods generated from the residues of the powers of 2 and 3 relative to modulus 7. In the case of 7, 3 is a primitive root, whereas 2 is not.)

These periods are completed periods and are not altered when all the elements are multiplied by any number. For example, multiply {1, 2, 4, 3} by any number, and take the residues relative to modulus 5. The resulting period will be the same as the one you started with. Similarly, for the period {1, 3, 4, 2}. (The reader is strongly encouraged to perform these experiments.)

Each complete period also has the two sub-periods. For the case of modulus 5, those sub- periods are {1, 4} and {2, 3}, which “orbit” each other. When either sub-period is multiplied by 2 or 3, they are transformed into the other. When multiplied by 1 or 4, they remain unchanged.

Similarly, the modulus 7 produces the period of residues, {1, 3, 2, 6, 4, 5, 1, 3, 2, 6, 4, 5} with respect to the powers of 3. It contains 2 sub-periods of 3 elements each, {1, 2, 4} and {3, 6, 5 } and 3 sub-periods of 2 elements each, {1,6}, {3, 4}, and {2, 5}. (Much will be gained if the reader tries multiplying the elements of each sub-period to see what transformations occur.)

Modulus 17 produces the period of residues, {1, 3, 9, 10, 13, 5, 15, 11, 16, 14, 8, 7, 4, 12, 2, 6} with respect to the powers of 3. It contains 2 sub-periods of 8, {1, 9, 13, 15, 16, 8, 4, 2} and {3, 10, 5, 11, 14, 7, 12, 6}; 4 sub-sub-periods of 4, {1, 13, 16, 4}; {9, 15, 8, 2}; {3, 5, 14, 12}; and {10, 11, 7, 6}. And, finally, 8 sub-sub-sub-periods of 2, {1, 16}, {3, 14}, {9, 8}, {10, 7}, {13, 4}, {5, 12}, {15, 2}, {11, 6}.

Notice that in all cases, the sum of the numbers of a period or sub-period is always congruent to 0 relative to the modulus, and that the lengths of all periods are always the modulus minus 1 or a factor of the modulus minus 1.

The Determination of the Polygon’s Orbits

Being an artifact of an action in the complex domain, these individual vertices each corresponds to a complex number. The “n” complex numbers, corresponding to the “n” vertices, of an “n” sided polygon, comprise a complete period of “n” roots. The problem Gauss confronted was how to determine the positions of the individual vertices (“orbits”) of a polygon ?

Gauss’ discovery was to show that each of these “orbits” was completely determined by the harmonic nature of the whole. That harmonic principle is reflected in the nested chain of periods and sub-periods of the residues of powers. Gauss worked by inversion. Like Kepler with planetary orbits, Gauss understood that the harmonic principle determined the individual positions, so he developed a method to work from the top down, that is, from the harmonies to the notes, so to speak, showing how to “read” this chain of periods and sub-periods to determine the positions of the vertices, (“orbits”) of the polygon.

For pedagogical purposes it is most efficient to illustrate by continuing with the example of the pentagon.

The first step in determining the vertices of the pentagon is organize the vertices into a “harmonic” period. As was shown last week, all the vertices can be generated as a series of powers from any one of them. Therefore, Gauss began with one of the vertices and generated all the others as a series of powers. But, to bring out the “harmonic” characteristic, they had to be ordered according to the principle exhibited by the residues of the primitive root. Continuing from the example of the pentagon from last week, that would mean generating the period from the powers of a2^0, a2^1, a2^2 and a2^3. Taking the residues of these periods relative to modulus 5, these vertices will now be in the order, {1, 2, 4, 3}.

This period of can be divided into the two sub-periods {1, 4} and {2, 3}, that define the first set of magnitudes required to construct the pentagon. To determine the value of these magnitudes, Gauss considered them as “roots”, and since there are two of them, they must be “roots” of a quadratic equation. Call the value of {1, 4}= r1 and the value of {2, 3} = r2.

Here again Gauss worked by inversion. Even without knowing what the values for r1 and r2 are, except that they are “roots” of some quadratic equation, Gauss could work backwards from the harmonic relationship between them, to determine what must produce them.

To solve this problem, Gauss relied on the relationship between the roots and coefficients of algebraic equations (introduced without demonstration). That relationship is that if a quadratic equation is in the form x2 + Ax + B = 0, the sum of the roots equals -A and the product of the roots equals B.

Back to our example. Even without knowing the values of the individual vertices, we can know the sum and the products of them. The sum of the sub-periods {1, 4} and {2, 3} is {1 + 2 + 4 + 3}. This means adding together the complex numbers that correspond to the vertices 1, 2, 4, 3. Each complex number denotes a complex quantity of combined rotation and extension. To add complex numbers, you carry out the rotation and extension in series. In this example, you first carry out the rotation and extension that produces vertex 1. Then from the endpoint of vertex 1, carry out the rotation and extension that corresponds to vertex 2, and so forth. Geometrically, this turns the “inside-out” pentagon, “inside in”. (See figure.) From this it can be seen that the sum of 1 + 2 + 3 + 4 = -1.

Similarly, we can also determine the product of the sub-periods, even without knowing the values of the individual vertices. The product of the sub-periods {1, 4} and {2, 3} is {(1 + 2) + (1 + 3) + (4 + 2) + (4 + 3)}. Taking the residues relative to modulus 5 this equals {3 + 4 + 1 + 2} which also equals -1. (See figure.) ( This is also evident from the fact that 1 x 4 x 2 x 3 = 24 which is congruent to -1 mod 5.)

Therefore {1, 4} and {2, 3} are the “roots” of the quadratic equation where A = 1 and B = -1, or, x2 + x – 1 = 0. That means the {1, 4} = r1 = (-1+?5)/2 and {2, 3} = r2 = (-1-?5)/2.

The final step for the construction of the pentagon is to find the two vertices from the just discovered values of each sub-period. For example, the vertices 1 and 4are the “roots” of the sub- period {1, 4}, and the vertices 2 and 3, are the “roots” of the sub-period {2, 3}.

In sum, the action that generates the pentagon is a nested chain of second degree actions, and therefore, “knowable” geometrically.

What Gauss has demonstrated in general, is that any polygon is generated by a nested series of actions determined by the periods and sub-periods formed by the residues of powers. Since the number and length of these periods and sub-periods is determined by the factors of the modulus minus 1, the degree (or power) of each action will be determined by these factors.

For example, the construction of the heptagon will be determined by one cubic and one quadratic action. The 11-gon will be determined by one fifth power and one quadratic action; the 13-gon by one cubic and two quadratic actions; the 19-gon by two cubics and one quadratic action.

On the other hand, the 17-gon, 257-gon, the 65, 537-gon are all generated by a chain of quadratic powers, and are therefore geometrically “knowable”

Anyone who makes the effort to re-live this discovery of the 18 year old Gauss, will discover a corresponding increase in their own cognitive power.

Riemann for Anti-Dummies: Part 30 : The Powers of One

Riemann For Anti-Dummies Part 30

THE POWERS OF ONE

On the morning of March 30, 1796, Carl Friedrich Gauss discovered that the way people had been thinking for more than 2000 years was wrong. That was the day, when, after an intensive period of concentration, he saw on a deeper level than anyone before, the “profound connection” between transcendental magnitudes and higher Arithmetic.

The first public announcement of his discovery was at the initiative of E.A.W. Zimmerman, a collaborator of Abraham Kaestner, who headed the Collegium Carolineum, the school for classical studies, where Gauss had received his preparatory education. The notice was carried in the April 1796 issue of Allgemeine Literaturzeitung:

“It is known to every beginner in geometry that various regular polygons, namely the triangle; tetragon; pentagon; 15-gon, and those which arise by the continued doubling of the number of sides of one of them, are geometrically constructable.

“One was already that far in the time of Euclid, and, it seems, it has generally been said since then that the field of elementary geometry extends no farther; at least I know of no successful attempt to extend its limits on this side.

“So much the more, methinks, does the discovery deserve attention, that in addition to those ordinary polygons there is still another group, for example the 17-gon, that are capable of geometric construction. This discovery is really only a special corollary to a theory of greater scope, not yet completed, and is to be presented to the public as soon as it has received its completion.”

Carl Friedrich Gauss
Student of Mathematics at Goettingen

“It deserves mentioning, that Mr. Gauss is now in his 18th year, and devoted himself here in Brunswick with equal success to philosophy and classical literature as well as higher mathematics.”

E.A.W. Zimmerman, Prof.

Gauss did not construct the 17-gon. As the announcement indicates, the constructability of the 17-gon is merely a corollary of a much deeper principle–the generation of magnitudes of higher powers, as that principle was understood by Plato, Cusa, Kepler, Fermat, Leibniz and the Bernoulli’s. As with his contemporaneous work on the fundamental theorem of algebra, Gauss’ approach was explicitly anti-deductive, discovering a common physical principle that underlay both geometry and number. It was also a direct confrontation with the failed Aristotelean methods of the likes of Euler and Lagrange who understood the circle as an object in visible space and numbers as abstract formalisms.

Today’s pedagogical exercise is the first of two, intended to guide the reader through the relevant concepts of Gauss’ method. It will require some “heavy lifting” and the reader is advised to work it through all the way to the end, no matter how arduous it seems along the way, and then look back, surveying what has been gained from the vantage point of the summit. The reader is also advised to review the preliminary work on Gauss’ theory of the division of the circle that was the subject of the several past pedagogicals, as it was summarized in the Winter 2001-2002 edition of 21st Century Science and Techonlogy, and the pedagogical exercises on the residues of powers (Riemann for Anti-Dummies Parts 20-25.) (Reference will also be made to several figures)

Polygons As Powers

As Gauss’ announcement indicates, by Euclid’s time, geometers had succeeded in finding the magnitudes that divided a circle in certain ways. What was not so evident, was why those ways and not others? From the standpoint of sense certainty, the circle, like the line, appears uniform and everywhere the same. Why then, is it not, like the line, divisible into whatever number of parts one desires? What unseen principle is determining which divisions are possible, and which are not?

Yet, when the circle is considered as a unit of action in the complex domain, it becomes evident that the division of the circle is based on the principle that generates magnitudes of successively higher powers. Those who have worked through the pedagogical exercises on Gauss’ 1799 doctoral dissertation are familiar with how this works. There we saw that algebraic powers are generated by a non-algebraic, physical principle, as expressed, for example, by the catenary. This principle belongs to the domain of functions that Leibniz called transcendentala, and is expressed mathematically by the equiangular spiral, or alternatively, the exponential (logarithmic) functions. Gauss showed that these transcendental functions were themselves part of a higher class of functions that could only be adequately known through images in the complex domain.

From this standpoint, the generation of magnitudes of any algebraic power correspond to an angular change within an equiangular spiral. “Squaring” is the action associated with doubling the angle within an equiangular spiral, “cubing” by tripling, fourth power by quadrupling, and so forth. These angular changes are, consequently, what generates magnitudes of succesively higher algebraic powers. When the circle is correctly understood as merely a special case of an equiangular spiral, the generation of algebraic powers is reflected as a mapping of one circle onto another. Squaring, for example, maps one circle onto another twice, cubing maps three times, and so on for the higher powers. (The reader is referred to the figures from the pedagogical discussions on the fundamental theorem of algebra.)

The regular divisions of the circle are simply the inversion of this action. Each rotation around the “squared” circle divides the original circle in half. Each rotation around the “cubed” circle divides the original circle into thirds, each rotation around the fourth power circle, divides the original circle into fourths, and so on. Consequently, the vertices of a regular polygon, are the points on the original circle, that correspond to the complete rotations around the “powered” circle and the number of vertices corresponds to the degree of the power. For example, the fifth power will produce, by inversion, the five vertices of the pentagon; the inversion of the seventh power, will produce the seven vertices of the heptagon, etc. All the vertices of a given polygon are generated, “all at once”, so to speak, by one function, which is the inversion of the function that generates the corresponding power. (By Gauss’ time, such inversions had come to be called “roots”, not to be confused with the misapplication of that term by ignorant translators of Plato’s word, “dunamis”.) Herein lies the paradox. If the triangle, square and pentagon are inversions of the generation of third, fourth, and fifth powers respectively, how come they are constructable and other polygons are not? (Constructable is used here in the same sense as Kepler uses the term “knowable” in the first book of the Harmonies of the World. By “knowable”, Kepler meant those magnitudes that were commensurate with the diameter of the circle, part of the diameter, or the square of the diameter or its part. These magnitudes are the only magnitudes, “constructable” from the circle and its diameter, or by straight-edge and compass. All such magnitudes correspond to “square roots” or magnitudes of the second power. Magnitudes of higher powers, are not “knowable” from the circle alone, as is evident from the problem of doubling the cube, or trisecting the angle.)

Prime Numbers are Ones

It was Gauss’ insight to recognize that the solution to this paradox lay, not in the visible circle, but in the nature of prime numbers. To begin with, throw out the common formal definition of prime numbers, and consider a physical principle in which prime numbers arise. This can be most efficiently illustrated by example. Perform the following experiment: draw 10 dots, in a roughly circular configuration, and number them 0 to 9. Connect the 10 dots sequentially (0, 1, 2,…) and call that sequence 1. Now connect every other dot, (0, 2, 4, 6…) and call that action sequence 2. Then every third dot, (0, 3, 6, 9, …, for sequence 3) then every fourth dot, (0, 4, 8, …, sequence 4) and so on.

Notice, that some sequences succeeded in connecting all 10 dots, namely, sequences 1, 3, 7 and 9, while sequences 2, 4, 5, and 8 connected only some of the dots. In the case of the latter, sequences, 2 and 5 became completed actions within one rotation, whereas 4 and 8 did not become completed actions until after more than one rotation.

Numbers are not formal symbols (or objects), to be manipulated according to a set of formal rules, but are relationships arising from physical action. In the above example, the number 10 becomes a One, or, as Gauss called it, a modulus. The numbers 1 through 9 are types of actions, not collections of things. With respect to modulus 10, the numbers (actions) 1, 3, 7, and 9 are called relatively prime, because those actions do not divide the modulus. The numbers 2, and 5, are called factors of 10, because those actions do divide the modulus within one rotation. (The numbers 4 and 8, divide the modulus but not within one rotation because they are not factors themselves but they share a common factor (namely 2) with 10.)

These relationships, of factors and relative primeness, are determined only by the nature of the modulus. If you begin sequence 2 on dot #1 instead of dot #0, it still connects only 5 dots. Similarly, if you begin sequence 3 on dot #1, it will still be relatively prime to 10. Additionally, if you continue the experiment with sequences 11, 12, 13, etc., the results will be identical to the sequences 1, 2, 3, etc. except that one rotation will be added. Gauss called these numbers congruent relative to modulus 10.

Thus, the modulus defines certain relationships, relative to the entire universe of whole numbers, in which some numbers are factors, some numbers are relatively prime, and some numbers are not factors themselves, but contain factors of the modulus.

However, when one dot is added, and the same experiment is performed with respect to 11 dots, all the sequences connect all the dots. Thus, 11 has no factors and all numbers are relatively prime to it. The relationship of modulus 11 to the entire universe of whole numbers is quite different than the modulus 10.

The modulus is the One. Some moduli, such as 10, define some numbers as factors,and some numbers as relatively prime and are called “composite”. Those moduli under which all numbers are prime, are known as prime numbers.

There is nothing absolute about the quality of primeness. Relatively prime numbers gain this characteristic relative to a one (modulus). Those numbers that are prime relative to the One, are absolutely prime. (Gauss, in his treatises on bi-quadratic residues, would later show that even this characteristic of absolute primeness is not really absolute but relative to a still higher principle.)

Polygons as Planetary Systems

This leads us back to the original paradox. If the prime numbers are irreducible Ones, how come some prime number divisions of the circle are constructable and others not?

Take another look at the image of a circle in the complex domain. The vertices of a regular polygon are the roots (inversions) of a corresponding power. This relationship of “roots” and “powers” produces a type of harmonic “planetary system” for each polygon in which only those “planetary orbits” that correspond to the “roots” of that “power” are possible, and, these “roots” have a unique harmonic relationship to each other, whose characteristics are determined by the number-theoretic characteristics of the prime number.

Illustrate this pedagogically by an example. The vertices of a regular pentagon are the five “roots” of 1 and each of these “roots” is a complex number that has the power to produce a fifth degree magnitude. Such complex numbers represented the combined action of rotation and extension. Since in a circle the extension is constant, the complex numbers are at the endpoints of equally spaced radii. To construct the polygon it is necessary to determine the positions of these radii. To do this Gauss used the method of inversion and determined the positions of the radii from the harmonic relations among them. Even without knowing the positions of the radii, the harmonic relations can be known because the radii are inversions (roots) of powers. In other words, the vertices of the polygon are the endpoints of equally spaced radii.

But don’t look at the endpoints (visible objects). Look for why the radii are equally spaced. They are equally spaced because they are the roots of an algebraic power. To illustrate this use the pentagon as an example, draw a circle with five approximately equally spaced radii. This should look like an “inside out” pentagon. (Since we are investigating only the relationships among the radii at this point it is not necessary that the radii be exactly equally spaced.)

Label the endpoints of the radii 1, a, b, c, d, with “a” representing 1/5 of a rotation, “b”, 2/5, “c”, 3/5, “d”, 4/5 and “1” being 1 full rotation. If any of these individual angular actions is repeated (multiplied) five times, the resulting action will end up at 1. In other words, a5, b5, c5 and d5 are all equal to 1. Furthermore, a0=1, a1=a, a2=b, a3=c, a4=d; b0=1, b1=b, b2=d, b3=a, b4=c; c0=1, c1=c, c2=a,c3=d, c4=b; d0=1, d1=d, d2=c, d3=b, d4=a. Thus, any vertex can generate all the others. (For the general case, each of the vertices corresponds to a complex number of the form a + b ?-1, such that (a + b?-1)n =1 for all “n’s” of an “n” sided polygon.)

In the example of the pentagon, five is the modulus, the One, which establishes a certain harmonic ordering under which there are five and only five “orbits”. A different modulus would produce a different number of “orbits”, but the relationship just illustrated will remain; only the number of “orbits” will have changed, and consequently, the nature of the harmonies. Notice the congruence of these actions with our earlier experiment with dots illustrating the physical principle from which primeness, relative primeness and factors arise. Notice the similarity between the power sequences generated from each complex root, and the different number sequences used to connect the dots. This congruence is not discovered by looking at the visible objects, but by a method Leibniz called, “Geometry of Position”, or “analysis situs”, or what Gauss called, “geometrica situs”. It reflects a higher principle, independent of any particular number and begins to shed light on that “profound connection” Gauss discovered between the geometry of transcendental functions and higher Arithmetic.

Next week we’ll look further into that connection.

Riemann for Anti-Dummies: Part 29 : The Crimes of Klein

Riemann for Anti-Dummies Part 29

THE CRIMES OF KLEIN

When working through the conceptions underlying Gauss’ 1799 proof of the fundamental theorem of algebra, or, Gauss’ discovery of the principles behind the division of the circle (to take only two examples), one is immediately confronted with the fact that these discoveries arise from explicitly anti-deductive methods of thinking. Most difficulties experienced by modern students attempting to work through these discoveries, are rooted in the tendency of those individuals to revert to ingrained habits of deductive thinking, just at the point when only an explicitly anti-deductive, creative leap will do. “Where’s the cube in Archytus’ construction?”; “What exactly is Gauss trying to prove?”; “I understand what you said, but I still don’t understand what it means,” are some common symptoms of this affliction.

The serious person can take heart that such symptoms need not indicate an incurable condition, but it is only the recurring effects of the malicious teaching methods most people today have suffered through. It may be helpful to those suffering from these effects, to take a clinical look at how this “deductivizing” was introduced into modern educational practices by G.W.F. Hegel’s grandson-in-law, Felix Klein. As a talented mathematician, Klein was not as radical a reductionist or as openly fascistic as Russell, Kronecker or Helmholtz. Yet his method was pure Bogomilism, nevertheless. Rather than try and obliterate the creative discoveries of Leibniz, Gauss and Riemann, Klein adopted a seemingly “middle ground” so to speak, in which the discoveries were stripped of their creative insight, and re-cast in deductive, i.e. impotent, form.

While Klein had an extensive influence over the teaching methods of a wide domain of scientific subjects, it is sufficient, for our purposes at this moment, to look at his treatment of Gauss’ early discoveries, to obtain the clinical benefit of freeing those individuals, who, knowingly or not, have been victimized by Klein’s crime.

As discussed in the recent pedagogicals of this series, Gauss’ early discoveries have their origin in the paradoxes arising from the investigations of “powers” as that concept is defined by Plato, and how these paradoxes arise in the classical problems of doubling the cube and trisecting an angle. For Plato, Cusa, Kepler, Leibniz, Kaestner, Gauss, Riemann, these investigations led into the deepest questions concerning the relationship of man to the universe. However, in his 1895 lectures, “Famous Problems of Elementary Geometry”, Klein reduces these problems to the following, which will seem uneasily familiar to most students today:

“In all these problems the ancients sought in vain for a solution with straight edge and compasses, and the celebrity of these problems is due chiefly to the fact that their solution seemed to demand the use of appliances of a higher order…”

This already is complete fraud. Plato’s circle did not consider the straight edge and compass as “appliances”, but as Kepler summarizes the question in the first book of the “Harmonies of the World”, the question under investigation was the “knowability” of magnitudes. That is, which magnitudes were “knowable” from the circumference and diameter of a circle, and which were “unknowable”.

Klein continues, “At the outset we must insist upon the difference between practical and theoretical constructions. For example, if we need a divided circle as a measuring instrument, we construct it simply on trial. Theoretically, in earlier times, it was possible (i.e. by the use of straight edge and compasses) only to divide the circle into a number of parts represented by 2n, 3 and 5 and their products. Gauss added other cases by showing the possibilty of the division into parts where p is a prime number of the form p = (22p) + 1, and the impossibility for all other numbers. No practical advantage is derived from these results; the significance of Gauss’ developments is purely theoretical.”

Klein’s separation of the theoretical and practical is pure evil Bogomilism, in addition to being a fraud. One need look no further, than Erathosthenes’ account of the history of the duplication of the cube, as reported by Theon of Smyrna:

“Eratosthenes in his work entitled “Plotinicus” relates that, when the god proclaimed to the Delians through the oracle that, in order to get rid of a plague, they should construct an altar double that of the existing one, their craftsmen fell into great perplexity in their efforts to discover how a solid could be made the double of a similar solid; they therefore went to ask Plato about it, and he replied that the oracle meant, not that the god wanted an altar of double the size, but that he wished, in setting them the task, to shame the Greeks for their neglect of mathematics and their contempt of geometry.”

Where is the separation of the theoretical from the practical in Eratosthenes account? Was it purely a theoretical matter, that the Delians had become so morally corrupt by their neglect of the cognitive powers of the mind, that they had become victims of a deadly plague?

As the Thirty Years War began to unfold in full horror, Kepler, on the occasion of the twenty-fifth anniversary of the publication of his “Mysterium Cosmographicum”, invoked the “practical” benefits of the power of cognition, “would that even now indeed there may still, after the reversal of Austrian affairs which followed, be a place for Plato’s oracular saying. For when Greece was on fire on all sides with a long civil war, and was troubled with all the evils which usually accompany civil war, he was consulted about a Delian Riddle, and was seeking a pretext for suggesting salutary advice to the peoples. At length he replied that, according to Apollo’s opinion Greece would be peaceful if the Greeks turned to geometry and other philosophical studies, as these studies would lead their spirits from ambition and other forms of greed, out of which wars and other evils arise, to the love of peace and to moderation in all things.”

And Gauss, himself, when installed as head of the Goettingen University Observatory, pronounced that the political troubles that had befallen Europe at that time, arose from a contempt for purely cognitive discoveries.

Klein is deadly wrong. Gauss’ discoveries were not purely theoretical. Recognizing that is crucial to being able to grasp elementary mathematics from a truly advanced, (LaRouchian) standpoint.

Riemann for Anti-Dummies: Part 28 : Bringing the Invisible to the Surface

Riemann for Anti-Dummies Part 28

BRINGING THE INVISIBLE TO THE SURFACE

When Carl Friedrich Gauss, writing to his former classmate Wolfgang Bolyai in 1798, criticized the state of contemporary mathematics for its “shallowness”, he was speaking literally – and, not only about his time, but also of ours. Then, as now, it had become popular for the academics to ignore, and even ridicule, any effort to search for universal physical principles, restricting the province of scientific inquiry to the, seemingly more practical task, of describing only what’s on the surface. Ironically, as Gauss demonstrated in his 1799 doctoral dissertation on the fundamental theorem of algebra, what’s on the surface, is revealed only if one knows, what’s underneath.

Gauss’ method was an ancient one, made famous in Plato’s metaphor of the cave, and given new potency by Johannes Kepler’s application of Nicholas of Cusa’s method of On Learned Ignorance. For them, the task of the scientist was to bring into view, the underlying physical principles, that could not be viewed directly-the unseen that guided the seen.

Take the illustrative case of Pierre de Fermat’s discovery of the principle, that refracted light follows the path of least time, instead of the path of least distance followed by reflected light. The principle of least-distance, is a principle that lies on the surface, and can be demonstrated in the visible domain. On the other hand, the principle of least-time, exists “behind”, so to speak, the visible, brought into view, only in the mind. On further reflection, it is clear, that the principle of least-time, was there all along, controlling, invisibly, the principle of least-distance. In Plato’s terms of reference, the principle of least-time is of a “higher power”, than the principle of least-distance.

Fermat’s discovery is a useful reference point for grasping Gauss’ concept of the complex domain. As Gauss himself stated, unequivocally, this is not Leonard Euler’s formal, superficial concept of “impossible” numbers (a fact ignored by virtually all of today’s mathematical “experts”). Rather, Gauss’ concept of the complex domain, like Fermat’s principle of least-time, brings to the surface, a principle that was there all along, but hidden from view.

As Gauss emphasized in his jubilee re-working of his 1799 dissertation, the concept of the complex domain is a “higher domain”, independent of all a priori concepts of space. Yet, it is a domain, “in which one cannot move without the use of language borrowed from spatial images.”

The issue for Gauss, as for Gottfried Leibniz, was to find a general principle, that characterized what had become known as “algebraic” magnitudes. These magnitudes, associated initially, with the extension of lines, squares, and cubes, all fell under Plato’s concept of “dunamais”, or “powers”.

Leibniz had shown, that while the domain of all “algebraic” magnitudes consisted of a succession of higher powers, the entire algebraic domain, was itself dominated by a domain of a still higher power, that Leibniz called, “transcendental”. The relationship of the lower domain of algebraic magnitudes, to the higher non-algebraic domain of transcendental magnitudes, is reflected in, what Jacob Bernoulli discovered about the equiangular spiral. (See Figure 1.)

Figure 1

Leibniz and Johann Bernoulli (Jakob’s brother) subsequently demonstrated that his higher, transcendental domain, exists not as a purely geometric principle, but originates from the physical action of a hanging chain, whose geometric shape Christaan Huygens called a catenary. (See Figure 2.) Thus, the physical universe itself demonstrates, that the “algebraic” magnitudes associated with extension, are not generated by extension. Rather, the algebraic magnitudes are generated from a physical principle that exists, beyond simple extension, in the higher, transcendental, domain.

Figure 2

Gauss, in his proofs of the fundamental theorem of algebra, showed that even though this transcendental physical principle was outside the visible domain, it nevertheless cast a shadow that could be made visible in what Gauss called the complex domain.

As indicated in “Gauss’ Declaration of Independence,” the discovery of a general principle for “algebraic” magnitudes was found, by looking through the “hole” represented by the square roots of negative numbers, which could appear as solutions to algebraic equations, but lacked any apparent physical meaning. For example, in the algebraic equation x2 = 4, “x” signifies the side of a square whose area is 4, while, in the equation x2 = -4, the “x” signifies the side of a square whose area is -4, an apparent impossibility. For the first case, it is simple to see, that a line whose length is 2 would be the side of the square whose area is 4. However, from the standpoint of the algebraic equation, a line whose length is -2, also produces the desired square.

At first glance, a line whose length is -2 seems as impossible as a square whose area is -4. Yet, if you draw a square of area 2, you will see that there are two diagonals, both of which have the power to produce a new square whose area is 4. These two magnitudes are distinguished from one another only by their direction, so one is denoted as 2 and the other as -2.

Now extend this investigation to the cube. In the algebraic equation x3 = 8, there appears to be only one number, 2 which satisfies the equation, and this number signifies the length of the edge of a cube whose volume is 8. This appears to be the only solution to this equation since -2x – 2x – 2 = -8.

The anomaly that there are two solutions, which appeared for the case of a quadratic equation, seems to disappear, in the case of the cube, for which there appears to be only one solution.

Not so fast. Look at another geometrical problem, that, when stated in algebraic terms, poses the same paradox–the trisection of an arbitrary angle. Like the doubling of the cube, Greek geometers could not find a means for equally trisecting an arbitrary angle, from the principle of circular action itself. The several methods discovered, (by Archimedes, Erathosthenes, and others), to find a general principle of trisecting an angle, were similar to those found, by Plato’s collaborators, for doubling the cube. That is, this magnitude could not be constructed using only a circle and a straight line, but it required the use of extended circular action, such as conical action.

But, trisecting an arbitrary angle presents another type of paradox which is not so evident in the problem of doubling the cube. To illustrate this, make the following experiment:

Draw a circle. For ease of illustration, mark off an angle of 60 degrees. It is clear that an angle of 20 degrees will trisect this angle equally. Now add one circular rotation to the 60 degree angle, making an angle of 420 degrees. It appears these two angles are essentially the same. But, when 420 is divided by 3 we get an angle of 140 degrees. Add another 360 degree rotation and we get to the angle of 780 degrees, which appears to be exactly the same as the angles of 60 and 420 degrees. Yet, when we divide 780 degrees by 3 we get 260 degrees. Keep this up, and you will see that the same pattern is repeated over and over again. (See Figure 3.)

Figure 3

Looked at from the domain of sense certainty, the angle of 60 degrees can be trisected by only one angle, that is, an angle of 20 degrees. Yet, when looked at beyond sense certainty, there are clearly three angles that “solve” the problem.

This illustrates another “hole” in the algebraic determination of magnitude. In the case of quadratic equations, there seems to be two solutions to each problem. In some cases, such x2 = -4, those solutions seem to have a visible existence. While for the case, x2 = -4, there are two solutions, 2?-1 and -2?-1, both of which seem to be “imaginary”, having no physical meaning. In the case of cubic equations, sometimes there are three visible solutions, such as in the case of trisecting an angle. Yet, in the case of doubling the cube, there appears to be only one visible solution, but two “imaginary” solutions, specifically: -1 – ?3?-1, -1 + ?3?-1. Biquadratic equations, (for example x4 = 16) , that seem to have no visible meaning themselves, have four solutions, two “real” (2 and -2) and two “imaginary” (2?-1 and -2?-1). Things get even more confused for algebraic magnitudes of still higher powers. This anomaly poses the question that Gauss resolved in his proof of what he called the fundamental theorem of algebra; that is: how many solutions are there for any algebraic equation?

The “shallow” minded mathematicians of Gauss’ day, such as Euler, Lagrange, and D’Alembert, took the superficial approach of asserting that any algebraic equation has as many solutions as it has powers, even if those solutions were “impossible”, such as the square roots of negative numbers. (This sophist’s argument is analogous to saying there is a difference between man and beast, but, this difference is meaningless.)

Gauss, in his 1799 dissertation, polemically exposed this fraud for the sophistry it was. “If someone would say a rectilinear equilateral right triangle is impossible, there will be nobody to deny that. But, if he intended to consider such an impossible triangle as a new species of triangles and to apply to it other qualities of triangles, would anyone refrain from laughing? That would be playing with words, or rather, misusing them.”

For, Gauss, no magnitude could be admitted, unless its principle of generation was demonstrated. For magnitudes associated with the square roots of negative numbers, that principle was the complex physical action of rotation combined with extension. Magnitudes generated by this complex action, Gauss called “complex numbers” in which each complex number denoted a quantity of combined rotational and extended action. The unit of action in Gauss’ complex domain is a circle, which is one rotation with an extension of unit length. The number 1 signifies one complete rotation, -1 one half a rotation, ?-1 one fourth a rotation, and -?-1 three fourths a rotation. (See Figure 4.)

Figure 4

These “shadows of shadows”, as he called them, were only a visible reflection of a still higher type of action, that was independent of all visible concepts of space. These higher forms of action, although invisible, could nevertheless be brought into view as a projection onto a surface.

Gauss’ approach is consistent with that employed by the circles of Plato’s Academy, as indicated by their use of the term “epiphanea” for surface, which comes from the same root as the word, “epiphany”. The concept indicated by the word “epiphanea” is, ” that on which something is brought into view”.

From this standpoint, Gauss demonstrated, in his 1799 dissertation, that the fundamental principle of generation of any algebraic equation, of no matter what power, could be brought into view, “epiphanied”, so to speak, as a surface in the complex domain. These surfaces were visible representations, not, as in the cases of lines, squares and cubes, of what the powers produced, but of the principle that produced the powers.

To construct these surfaces, Gauss went outside the simple visible representation of powers, such as squares and cubes, by seeking a more general form of powers, as exhibited in the equiangular spiral. (See Figure 5.) Here, the generation of a power, corresponds to the extension produced by an angular change. For example, the generation of square powers, corresponds to the extension that results from a doubling of the angle of rotation around the spiral.

Figure 5

The generation of cubed powers corresponds to the extension that results from tripling the angle of rotation. Thus, it is the principle of squaring that produces square magnitudes, and the principle of cubing that produces cubics. (See figure 6.)

Figure 6

For example, in Figure 7 , the complex number z is “squared” when the angle of rotation is doubled from x to 2x and the length squared from A to A2. In doing this, the smaller circle maps twice onto the larger “squared” circle.

Figure 7

In Figure 8, the same principle is illustrated with respect to cubing. Here the angle x is tripled to 3x, and the length A is cubed to A3. In this case, the smaller circle maps three times onto the larger, “cubed” circle.

Figure 8

And so on for the higher powers. The fourth power maps the smaller circle four times onto the larger. The fifth power, five times, and so forth.

This gives a general principle that determines all algebraic powers, as, from this standpoint, all powers are reflected by the same action. The only thing that changes with each power, is the number of times that action occurs. Thus, each power is distinguished from the others, not by a particular magnitude, but by a topological characteristic.

In his doctoral dissertation, Gauss used this principle to generate surfaces that expressed the essential characteristic of powers in an even more fundamental way. Each rotation and extension, produced a characteristic right triangle. The vertical leg of that triangle is called the sine and the horizontal leg of that triangle is called the cosine. (See Figure 9.)

Figure 9

There is a cyclical relationship between the sine and cosine which is a function of the angle of rotation. When the angle is 0, the sine is 0 and the cosine is 1. When the angle is 90 degrees the sine is 1 and the cosine is 0. Looking at this relationship for an entire rotation, the sine goes from 0 to 1 to 0 to -1 to 0, while the cosine goes from 1 to 0 to -1 to 0 and back to 1. (See Figure 10)

Figure 10

In Figure 9, as z moves from 0 to 90 degrees, the sine of the angle varies from 0 to 1, but at the same time, the angle for z2 goes from 0 to 180 degrees, and the sine of z2 varies from 0 to 1 and back to 0. Then as z moves from 90 degrees to 180 degrees, the sine varies from 1 back to 0, but the angle for z2 has moved from 180 degrees to 360 degrees, and its sine has varied from 0 to -1 to 0. Thus, in one half rotation for z, the sine of z2 has varied from 0 to 1 to 0 to -1 to 0.

In his doctoral dissertation, Gauss represented this complex of actions as a surface. (See Figures 11, 12, 13.) Each point on the surface is determined so that its height above the flat plane, is equal to the distance from the center, times the sine of the angle of rotation, as that angle is increased by the effect of the power. In other words, the power of any point in the flat plane, is represented by the height of the surface above that point. Thus, as the numbers on the flat surface move outward from the center, the surface grows higher according to the power. At the same time, as the numbers rotate around the center, the sine will pass from positive to negative. Since the numbers on the surface are the powers of the numbers on the flat plane, the number of times the sine will change from positive to negative, depends on how much the power changes the angle (double for square powers, triple for cubics, etc.). Therefore, each surface will have as many “humps” as the equation has dimensions. Consequently, a quadratic equation will have two “humps” up and two “humps” down (Figure 11).

Figure 11

A cubic equation will have three “humps” up and three “humps” down. (Figure 12). A fourth degree equation four “humps” in each direction, (Figure 13), and so on.

Figure 12

Figure 13

Gauss specified the construction of two surfaces for each algebraic equation, one based on the variations of the sine and the other based on the variations of the cosine. (See figures 14a and 14b.)

Figure 14a

Figure 14b

Each of these surfaces will define definite curves where the surfaces intersect the flat plane. The number of curves will depend on the number of “humps” which in turn depend on the highest power. Since each of these surfaces will be rotated 90 degrees to each other, these curves will intersect each other, and the number of intersections, will correspond to the number of powers. (See figures 15a and 15b.) If the flat plane is considered to be 0, these intersections will correspond to the solutions, or “roots” of the equation. Thus, proving that an algebraic equation has as many roots as its highest power.

Figure 15a

Figure 15b

Step back and look at this work. These surfaces were produced, not from visible squares or cubes, but from the general principle of squaring, cubing, and higher powers. They represent, metaphorically, a principle that manifests itself physically, but cannot be seen. By projecting this principle, the general form of Plato’s powers, onto these complex surfaces, Gauss has brought the invisible into view, and made intelligible, something that is incomprehensible in the superficial world of algebraic formalism.

The effort to make intelligible the implications of the complex domain was a focus for Gauss throughout his life. Writing to his friend Hansen on December 11, 1825, Gauss said: “These investigations lead deeply into many others, I would even say, into the Metaphysics of the theory of space, and it is only with great difficulty can I tear myself away from the results that spring from it, as, for example, the true metaphysics of negative and complex numbers. The true sense of the square root of -1 stands before my mind fully alive, but it becomes very difficult to put it in words; I am always only able to give a vague image that floats in the air.”

It is here, that Riemann begins.

Riemann for Anti-Dummies: Part 27 : Gauss’ Declaration of Independence

Riemann for Anti-Dummies Part 27

GAUSS’ DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE

In September 1798, after three years of self-directed study, C.F. Gauss, then 21 years old, left Goettingen University without a diploma. He returned to his native city of Brunswick to begin the composition of his “Disquisitiones Arithmeticae.” lacking any prospect of employment, he hoped to continue receiving his student stipend. After several months of living on credit, word came from the Duke that the stipend would continue, provided Gauss obtained his doctor of philosophy degree, a task Gauss thought a distraction and wished to postpone.

Nevertheless, he took the opportunity to produce a virtual declaration of independence from the stifling world of deductive mathematics, in the form of a written thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of Helmstedt, on a new proof of the fundamental theorem of algebra. Within months, he was granted his doctorate without even being required to appear for oral examination.

Describing his intention to his former classmate, Wolfgang Bolyai, Gauss wrote, “The title indicates quite definitely the purpose of the essay; only about a third of the whole, nevertheless, is used for this purpose, the remainder contains chiefly the history and a critique of works on the same subject by other mathematicians (viz. d’Alembert, Bougainville, Euler, de Foncenex, Lagrange, and the encyclopedists … which latter, however, will probably not be much pleased) besides many and varied comments on the shallowness which is so dominant in our present-day mathematics.”

In essence, Gauss was defending, and extending, a principle, that goes back to Plato, in which only physical action, not arbitrary assumptions, defines our notion of magnitude. Like Plato, Gauss also recognized it were not sufficient to simply state his discovery, without a polemical attack on the Aristotelean falsehoods that had become so popular among his contemporaries.

Looking back on his dissertation 50 years later, Gauss said, “The demonstration is presented using expressions borrowed from the geometry of position, for in this way, the greatest acuity and simplicity is obtained. Fundamentally, the essential content of the entire argument belongs to a higher domain, independent from space, (i.e., anti-Euclidean) in which abstract general concepts of magnitudes, are investigated as combinations of magnitudes connected by continuity, a domain, which, at present, is poorly developed, and in which one cannot move without the use of language borrowed from spatial images.”

It is the intention of this installment to provide a summary sketch of the history of this conception, and Gauss’ development of it. Because of the difficulties of this medium, it can not be exhaustive. Rather, it seeks to outline the steps which should form the basis for extended oral pedagogical dialogues, such as is already underway in various locations.

Multiply-Extended Magnitude

A physical concept of magnitude was already fully developed by those circles associated with Plato, expressed most explicitly in the Meno, Theatetus, and Timaeus dialogues. Plato and his circle demonstrated this concept, pedagogically, through the paradoxes that arise when considering the uniqueness of the five regular solids, and the related problems of doubling a line, square, and cube. As Plato emphasized, each species of action, generated a different species of magnitude. He denoted such magnitudes by the Greek term, “dunamais”, a term akin to Leibniz’ use of the word “kraft”, translated into English as “power”. That is, a linear magnitude has the “power” to double a line, while only a magnitude of a different species has the “power” to double the square, and a still different species has the “power” to double a cube. (See figures 1a, 1b and 1c). In Riemann’s language, these magnitudes are called, respectively, simply, doubly, and triply extended. Plato’s circle emphasized that magnitudes of lesser extension lacked the capacity to generate magnitudes of higher extension, creating, conceptually, a succession of “higher powers”.

Riemann for Anti-Dummies: Part 26 : Ideas Cast Shadows, Too

Riemann for Anti-Dummies, Part 26

IDEAS CAST SHADOWS, TOO

It can be a source of confusion for the naive, and a means of deception of the wicked, to restrict the meaning of Plato’s metaphor of the cave, to those objects that originate outside of one’s skin. As all great scientists have come to know, ideas cast shadows, too. A true scientist never mistakes the shadows for the idea, seeking instead to discover the idea from between the shadows. Those who merely manipulate shadows are called sophists.

This defines the clear distinction between the concept of the complex domain of Gauss and Riemann, and the sophistry of Euler, Lagrange and D’Alembert. The former understood complex numbers as a simple case of a hierarchy of multiply extended magnitudes, or as Gauss called them, “shadows of shadows.” The latter considered complex numbers, “impossible,” but susceptible to complicated, but ultimately meaningless, symbolic manipulation, whose very complexity is intended to obscure its trickery.

A passion for sophistry pervades modern academia, as exemplified by J. E. Hofmann, who penned the forward to the 1970 republication of Abraham Kaestner’s “Geschichte der Mathematik.” As LaRouche indicated in footnote 42 of his new piece, “At the End of a Delusion,” Hofmann complains that Kaestner did not show sufficient respect for the achievements of the great mathematicians of his time Euler, Lagrange, and D’Alembert. It is precisely Kaestner’s disrespect for these sophists for which he deserves our great admiration and respect today. As the history of the discovery of the complex domain demonstrates, Hofmann’s blunder is not only a matter of a lack of comprehension of the subject, it is also indicative of the illiteracy of modern academia.

Hofmann’s error is immediately exposed by examining the 1799 doctoral dissertation of Kaestner’s student Carl F. Gauss, on “A Proof of the Fundamental Theorem of Algebra.” There, the 22 year old Gauss, matriculating for his doctorate under Kaestner, openly and explicitly castigates, Euler, Lagrange, and D’Alembert as sophists on the matter of the existence of complex numbers, showing the same disregard for Euler, Lagrange, D’Alembert, for which Hofmann cricizes Kaestner.

It is revealing that all modern biographers of Gauss have gone out of their way to dismiss Gauss’ relationship to Kaestner, who Gauss called, “A poet among mathematicians and a mathematician among poets..” It was Kaestner, the passionate defender of Leibniz and Kepler, the host of America’s Benjamin Franklin, who first raised the questions leading to the development of anti-Euclidean geometry, and, who provoked the young Gauss into deciding to pursue a life of scientific investigation. Kaestner’s biting wit and sharp-tongued polemics against the sophistry of Euler, Lagrange, and D’Alembert, the fools who would fall for their methods, sticks in the craw of the his Romantic enemies to this day. While Gauss never adopted the polemical style of his teacher, he shared Kaestner’s contempt for “ivory tower” sophistry, and expressed it in his life’s work, as a plain reading of 1799 doctoral thesis shows. After Kaestner’s death in 1800 and the ensuing rise of the fascist Napoleon, Gauss became more circumspect in his public pronouncements, but his distaste for what he called, “the screeching of the Beothians” never waned.

While a fuller account of this history must still be elaborated, it can already be stated without equivocation, that those who demean Kaestner, and hold Euler, Lagrange, and D’Alembert in high esteem, do so in defense of the degraded conception of man that produced modern fascism.

The next installment will provide a pedagogical presentation of Gauss’ doctoral thesis. This week focuses on the essential pre-history of the development of complex numbers.

As discussed in “Riemann for Anti-Dummies Part 18; ‘Doing the Impossible,'” the possible existence of complex numbers was posed in a paradox by Cardan in 1545. In his Ars Magna, Cardan pointed to the existence of what he called a “subtile” magnitude through a specific problem, to wit: “Find two numbers that add up to 10 and when multiplied together equal 40.”

Cardan recognized that this problem contained the paradox that arises from the difference between a line and a surface, because addition implies linear magnitudes, while multiplication implies a surface.

Begin with a line AB which has a length of 10. Divide the line into two parts, that produce the maximum area when multiplied together, which will be two segments of 5, which when multiplied together produce an area of 25. The sought after area is 40. Subtract 40 from 25 which yields an area of -15, which is produced by (?-15)(?-15). Thus, if you add ?-15 to one of the segments of 5 and subtract it from the other, the problem is solved, since (5 + ?-15) + (5 – ?-15) = 10; and (5 + ?-15)(5 – ?-15) = 40!

“This subtility results from arithmetic of which this final point is as I have said as subtile as it is useless,” Cardan proclaimed perplexed.

The paradox arises when one limits the conception of magnitudes to the sense perception characteristics of lines and areas, resulting (in Cardan’s example) in a magnitude of negative area.

A similar paradox arises in an even similar example. Think of a line segment of length x. Now think of a different line segment of length y. Now think of adding x to y to produce the line segment z. No matter what length you choose for x and y, you will always be able to think of a line segment whose length is z. In other words, one extensible magnitude added to another extensible magnitude, produces a third extensible magnitude.

But, what happens when you try and subtract one extensible magnitude from another? No problem if you try and subtract a smaller magnitude from a larger. But, if you try and subtract a larger extended magnitude from a smaller, you get a negative length! (For this reason negative numbers were often referred to as “false” numbers.)

It’s as if subtracting a larger line from a smaller, or a larger area from a smaller, pokes us into a world, that includes objects other than lengths and areas. Or, we must recognize that lengths and areas are only shadows and should not be mistaken for the {idea} of extended magnitude. To comprehend the {idea}, we have to go behind the shadows, by “seeing” between them. Subtracting a longer line from a shorter one, shows us a world of extensible magnitudes that exist behind the visible sense perceptions of magnitudes associated with lengths, and reveals that a more general idea of magnitude must include not only length, but also direction.

The paradox arising from subtracting a larger area from a smaller one, areas, proves more subtile. As we reviewed in Part 18, Leibniz and Huygens corresponded on the implications of the existence of the square roots of negative numbers, of which Huygens would say, “there is something hidden there which is incomprehensible to us.”

To which Leibniz would reply, “The imaginary number is a fine and wonderful recourse of the divine spirit, almost an amphibian between being and non-being.”

By contrast Euler, Lagrange and D’Alembert would prove adept at complicated manipulations of algebraic equations that included the square roots of negative numbers, while insisting at all times that such magnitudes were “impossible.”

This is precisely the issue that the young Gauss attacked in his proof of the fundamental theorem of algebra. These were not “impossible” magnitudes, Gauss insisted, but “shadows of shadows.” One can think of an image of such shadows by thinking of a unit circle in the complex domain divided by two perpendicular diameters, which intersect the circumference of the circle at 1, -1, ?-1, -?-1. Think of a point rotating counter-clockwise around this circle. Now think of the image of that point, as if it were observed by looking at the circle edge on. One would only see a point moving back and forth along a line from 1 to -1 and back again. In other words, the so-called “imaginary” part is always there, but you have to look behind the shadows to “see” it.

As Gauss told his friend Hansen in 1811:

“These investigations lead deeply into many others, I would even say, into the Metaphysics of the theory of space, and it is only with great difficulty can I tear myself away from the results that spring from it, as, for example, the true metaphysics of negative and complex numbers. The true sense of the square root of -1 stands before my mind (Seele) fully alive, but it becomes very difficult to put it in words; I am always only able to give a vague image that floats in the air.”

Riemann for Anti-Dummies: Part 25 : Schiller and Gauss

Riemann for Anti-Dummies Part 25

SCHILLER AND GAUSS

In his “Aesthetic Estimation of Magnitude”, Friedrich Schiller discusses a crucial ontological paradox that confronts science when it tries to exceed existing axiomatic assumptions:

“The power of imagination, as the spontaneity of emotion, accomplishes a twofold business in conceptualizing magnitude. It first gathers every part of the given quantum into an empirical consciousness, which is {apprehension}; secondly, it assembles the {successively collected} parts into a pure self-consciousness, in which latter business, that of {comprehension}, it acts entirely as pure understanding. That concept of “I” (empirical consciousness), in other words, combines with each part of the quantum: and through reflection upon these successively performed syntheses, I recognize the identity of my “I” (pure self- consciousness) in this series as a whole; in this way, the quantum first becomes an object for me. I think A to B to C, and so forth, and while I watch my activity; as it were, I say to myself: in A, as well as in B, and in C, I am the acting subject.

“Apprehension takes place {successively}, and I grasp each partial conception after the other….The synthesis, however, takes place {simultaneously}, and through the concept of the self-identity of my “I” in all preceding syntheses, I transcend anew the temporal conditions under which they had occurred. All those different empirical conceptions held by my “I” lose themselves in a single pure self-consciousness; the subject, which had acted in A, and B, and C, and so forth, is I, the eternally identical self…

“If the power of reflection transgresses this limit, and seeks to bring together mental images, which already lie beyond the limit, into unity of self-consciousness, it will lose as much in clarity as it gains in scope. Between the circumference of the entirety of a mental image and the distinctness of its parts, is an ever insuperable, specific relationship, wherefore in each addition of a large quantum we lose as much backward as we gain forwards and when we have reached the end-point, we see the starting point vanish.”

Schiller is not referring to quanta, which have magnitude, simply with respect to quantity, but as Leibniz, Gauss and Riemann did, as {universal principles}:

“Everything which has parts, is a quantum. Every perception, every idea formed by comprehension, has a magnitude, just as the latter has a domain and the former a content. Quantity in general, therefore, cannot be meant, if one speaks about a difference of magnitude among objects. Here we speak about such a quantity as characteristically belongs to an object, that is to say, that which is not simply a {quantum}, but is at the same time a {magnum},”

Think of Schiller’s concept with respect to the successive discoveries of Kepler and Gauss concerning planetary motion. If we think of the position and speed of the planet at any given moment, as a quantum, it is indeterminable, except as that quantum is a characteristic of the whole orbit. In that sense, the indeterminable position and speed at the moment, becomes determinable, only as an interval, a part, of the whole orbit. The magnitude associated with that interval, is the area swept out. This, magnitude cannot be measured by the successive addition of the speeds and positions of the planet, which, owing to the non-uniformity of the orbit are indeterminate, but, only as these are grasped as an interval of the whole.

But, the orbits, in turn, are not self-defined, and their magnitudes are indeterminable as individual orbits. Rather, the magnitudes of the individual orbits can only be determined as intervals with respect to the harmonic ordering among all the orbits at once. Inversely, that harmonic ordering cannot be determined by successive addition of each individual orbit, but only as intervals of the whole.

Further, as Gauss’ investigation of the asteroids demonstrated, these harmonic orderings are themselves changing, according to a still higher harmonic ordering.

In other words, if we seek to determine the position and speed of the planet at any moment, we are stymied until we are led to the orbit as a whole. And, if we seek to determine the nature of an individual orbit, we are stymied anew, until we are led to all the orbits. And, further, if we try to determine the harmonic ordering of all the orbits, we will be once again stymied, until we are led to the ordering of the harmonic ordering. From this vantage point, the individual position and speed of the planet, which was our first object of investigation, recedes, as the deeper underlying principles come to the fore.

In the terms of Leibniz’ calculus, the differential can be known only as a function of the integral. Or, under Schiller’s idea, if each principle is thought of as a quantum, it can only be measured with respect to a magnum, which in turn, is a quantum, to a, higher, yet to be discovered magnum. In terms of Riemannian differential geometry, it is the highest principle, which determines all lower ones.

Seen in this way, the principle of Mind, of which Kepler speaks as governing the motion of the planet, is not a simple conception of a mind interacting one on one between the planet and the Sun, but a principle of Mind, as Schiller speaks of above, that comprehends its actions from a higher and higher standpoint, which determine, the seemingly indeterminable action in the small.

Gauss’ investigation of bi-quadratic residues, and his and Riemann’s further development of differential geometry, provide the pedagogical/epistemological capacity for our minds to grasp this concept.

For Gauss, as for Plato, Fermat, and Leibniz, individual numbers are not self-defined, but are rather defined by a higher principle, which Gauss called congruence. Each modulus, thus, defines a certain indivisible “orbit” in which all the numbers from 1 to the modulus minus 1, are ordered. The ordering within any individual “orbit” is itself a function of the characteristic of the modulus. For example, if the modulus is an odd-even prime number, such as 5, 13, 17, etc. -1 is a residue of the modulus minus 1 power, and ?-1 is the residue of the 1/4 the modulus minus 1 power. If the modulus is an odd-odd prime number, ?-1 never emerges. However, this characteristic of prime numbers, is not determined by the individual prime numbers, but is rather a function of the, still as yet undiscovered, “orbit”, that determines prime numbers.

This characteristic of number led Gauss to search for a higher principle, which he discovered by extending the concept of number from simply-extended magnitudes, to doubly- extended magnitudes, which he called complex numbers.

The significance of this is best grasped pedagogically, by way of an example directly out of Gauss’ second treatise on bi-quadratic residues.

Gauss thought of the complex domain as mapped onto a plane that is covered by a grid of equally spaced squares, the vertices of each square signify what Gauss called complex whole numbers. Each complex whole number is of the form a +bi, where i stands for ?-1, and a and b are whole numbers. Gauss called a2 + b2 the “norm” of the complex number. Gaussian prime numbers, are those complex whole numbers, whose norms are prime numbers.

Gauss’ example uses the complex prime number 5+4i. Taking this as the modulus, the entire complex domain is “partitioned” into diamonds, whose sides are the hypothenuses of right triangles whose legs are 5 and 4. (See last week’s pedagogical.) Each diamond encloses 41 (52 + 42) individual complex whole numbers, which are all incongruent to each other, relative to modulus 5+4i.

(You can illustrate this, if you take the diamond whose vertices are the complex numbers 0, 5+4i, 1+9i, -4+5i, as no two numbers within this diamond will be separated by doubly- extended interval greater than 5+4i. Now, construct another diamond whose vertices are 5+4i, 10+8i, 6+13i, 1+9i. Each complex number within this new diamond will all be incongruent to every other within the diamond, but, each complex number of the second diamond will be congruent to that complex number that is in the same relative position in the first diamond, specifically, the number whose difference with it is 5+4i.)

Gauss then takes the complex number 1+2i as a primitive root of 5+4i. To grasp the meaning of this concept, see what happens, geometrically, when 1+2i is raised successively to the powers, in a new type of geometric progression. First you have (1+2i)0 = 1; Next is (1+2i)1 = 1+2i; These two numbers define a triangle whose vertices are 0, 1, 1+2i. This will form a right triangle, whose legs are 1 and 2 with hypotenuse ?5. The angle at the vertex 0 will be 63.4349 degrees, the angle at 1 will be 90 degrees and the angle at 1+2i will be 26.5651 degrees. Now construct a similar triangle to this, using the hypotenuse of this first triangle, as the shorter leg, placing the 90 degree angle at the vertex 1+2i. This will define a new vertex at -3+4i, which is (1+2i)2. Repeat this process, constructing another similar triangle, with right angle at -3+4i, and the side 0, -3+4i as the short leg. This defines a new complex number, -11-2i, which is (1+2i)4.

This chain of similar right triangles, is but a general case of the famous chain of right triangles constructed by Theodorus, as reported by Theatetus in Plato’s dialogue.

Each new vertex of this chain of similar right triangles, is thus a new, higher, power of 1+2i, and all lie on a unique logarithmic spiral. In other words, as this particular logarithmic spiral winds its way around the complex domain, the complex whole numbers it intersects are the powers of 1+2i. Thus, the powers of 1+2i are determined by a higher principle, of logarithmic spiral action. They are as moments in a orbit, or orbits in a planetary system.

Gauss continued this process, by continuing this spiral, so as to define 41 (52 +42) powers of 1+2i, and investigated these spiral points in a complex domain, “partitioned” into diamonds by modulus 5+4i, with the beginning diamond having 0 at its center. (This is the diamond whose vertices are (-1/2 – 4i), (4 – i), (+4i), (-4 + 1/2 i).) Now think of these diamonds spreading out, partitioning the complex domain, as the spiral winds its way around. Each time the spiral intersects a complex whole number, that number will be a power of 1+2i, and that number will be inside a particular diamond. Gauss showed that the first 40 complex whole numbers the spiral intersects, will each be in a different relative place within their respective diamonds, than any other previous or succeeding one. In other words, each complex whole number the spiral intersects, will be congruent to only one of the complex whole numbers in the beginning diamond. Most importantly, the 10th power of (1+2i) would be congruent to i, the 20th power to -1, the 30th power to –i, and the 40th power to 1. Then the cycle would repeat!

And so, if we begin with individual numbers we soon see these numbers can not be self determined, and we are led to the generating principle of congruence. But, these congruences produce “orbits” which can not be self-determined and we are led to a still higher principle of extended magnitudes. With each successive step, the individual numbers recede and as the higher principles come more to the fore in our minds.

And, yes, there is a still higher principle at work which Gauss discovered was connected directly to the Kepler problem. This was indicated by one of the earliest entries in his diaries that read, “I have discovered an amazing connection between bi-quadratic residues and the lemniscate”.

Our investigation of this remark, will have to wait for a future installment.

Riemann for Anti-Dummies: Part 24 : Let There Be Light

Riemann for Anti-Dummies Part 24

LET THERE BE LIGHT

As you heard Riemann proclaim in the opening remarks of his Habilitation lecture, without a “general concept of multiply-extended magnitudes in which spatial magnitudes are comprehended,” you are left in the dark. You can not know the nature of the physical universe, the validity of an idea, the economic value of human activity, the strategic significance of a current, or historical, event, or your personal identity in the simultaneity of eternity, to name but a few of the more important matters on which one would wish to shed light. Yet, the principles to which Riemann refers are far too little understood by those who must urgently be able to make such judgements.

Referencing Gauss, Riemann cites two characteristics necessary for the determination of multiply-extended magnitudes, dimensionality and curvature, neither of which can be determined a priori, but only by physical measurement. Such magnitudes are not mathematical quantities, but are universal physical principles, produced by a manifold of physical action, and, are relative to the manifold, not absolute.

Take some examples from the arsenal of ideas built up over the course of this series to illustrate the point.

1. As Kepler demonstrated, the non-uniform elliptical planetary orbit defines the magnitude of action within an orbit, as equal areas, rather than the arbitrary mathematical magnitudes of equal arcs or equal angles. The solar system as a whole, in turn defines a magnitude of action for individual orbits, consistent with the five Platonic solids, and the principles of musical polyphony. Thus, the action of a planet at any moment can only be measured as a function of the whole orbit, which orbit in turn is measured as a function of the whole solar system. While the orbit defines one species of magnitude (equal areas) the solar system as a whole defines a distinct and different species of magnitude (harmonics), which “reach down” into all parts of the individual orbit, even though the latter cannot be derived simply from the former.

2. The shortest path of reflected light defines a magnitude of action measured by equal angles. The least time path of refracted light defines a magnitude of action measured by the proportionality of the sines of the angles of incidence and refraction. In other words, under reflection the angles measure the change in the direction of the light, while under refraction, the angles are determined by the sines. In the manifold of physical action of reflected light, there is no change in medium, consequently no change in velocity of light, and so the effect of the sines “disappears” into the equality of angles. But in the higher dimensional manifold of refraction, the truth comes out, that it is not the angles that measure the action, but the inverse, the transcendental magnitudes of the sines.

It is important to keep in mind, that in both these examples, “dimension” is not a mathematical construct, but is associated with a distinct physical principle, which is then associated with a distinct species of magnitude, and, as Riemann emphasizes, the number of dimensions is increased by the discovery of each new physical principles.

This concept of magnitude is consistent with Schiller’s expression in “On the Aesthetic Estimation of Magnitude”:

“All comparative estimation of magnitude, however, be it abstract or physical, be it wholly or only partly determined, leads only to relative, and never to absolute magnitude; for if an object actually exceeds the measure which we assume to be a maximum, it can still always be asked, by how many times the measure is exceeded. It is certainly a large thing in relation to its species, but yet not the largest possible, and once the constraint is exceeded, it can be exceeded again and again, into infinity. Now, however, we are seeking absolute magnitude, for this alone can contain in itself the basis of a higher order, since all relative magnitudes, as such, are like to one another. Since nothing can compel our mind to halt its business, it must be the mind’s power of imagination which sets a limit for that activity. In other words, the estimation of magnitude must cease to be logical, it must be achieved aesthetically.

“If I estimate a magnitude in a logical fashion, I always relate it to my cognitive faculty; if I estimate it aesthetically, I relate it to my faculty of sensibility. In the first case, I experience something about the object, in the second case, on the contrary. I only experience something within me, caused by the imagined magnitude of the object. In the first case I behold something outside myself, in the second, something within me. Thus, in reality, I am no longer measuring, I am no longer estimating magnitude, rather I myself become for the moment a magnitude to myself, and indeed an infinite one. That object which causes me to be an infinite magnitude to myself, is called sublime.”

Think in these terms about Gauss’ development of the complex domain in the context of his work on biquadratic residues, where Gauss demonstrates that it is actually impossible to construct a concept of magnitude devoid of dimensionality. As the discoveries that Plato made famous in his Meno, Theatetus, and Timaeus dialogues, action along a line, a surface, or a solid, is associated, in each case, with distinct species of magnitude. The species of magnitude, associated with the manifolds of lower dimensions, are found in the manifolds of higher dimensions but not vice versa. Consequently, a paradox arises, if one attempts to measure action in manifolds of higher dimensions, by magnitudes that are produced in a manifold of lower dimensionality.

Look at this from the standpoint of the simple operations with numbers, addition, subtraction, multiplication, division. (Riemann added Leibniz’ integration and differentiation, to the domain of simple operations, and this will be taken up in future installments.) As the Theatetus reports, addition of doubly-extended magnitudes, (i.e. areas) cannot be measured by simply-extended magnitudes (i.e. lines), and yet, until Gauss, all operations of Arithmetic were constrained by the underlying assumption that each manifold could be measured by the same species of magnitudes. This paradox reemerged from the Renaissance on, as the paradox associated with the ?-1. Cardan, Leibniz, Huygens, and Kaestner, all understood that this paradox required the need for a higher conception of magnitude, while Newton, Euler and others, dismissed this magnitude as “impossible” .

For Gauss, action in a doubly-extended manifold, could only be measured by doubly- extended magnitudes, which he called “complex numbers”. These numbers are determined by two actions, rotation and extension, or alternatively, simultaneous horizontal and vertical action, such as in the bubble of a carpenters level. (It is about time to replace the commonly used term “Cartesian coordinates” when referring to horizontal and vertical action, with the more historically and conceptually accurate, term, “Fermat coordinates”.)

From this standpoint look at the basic concepts of Arithmetic with respect to both simply- extended and doubly-extended magnitudes. Under Gauss’ concept of congruence, all numbers are ordered with respect to the interval between them or the modulus. With respect to simply- extended manifolds, that interval corresponds to a line segment. But, with respect to a doubly- extended manifold, that interval has two parts, up-down and back forth. Illustrate this with an example from Gauss’ second treatise on bi-quadratic residues. The modulus 5+2i “partitions” the entire complex domain, by a series of squares whose sides are the hypothenuses of right triangles whose legs are 5 and 2. For example, the square whose vertices are 0, 5+2i, 3+7i, – 2+5i. All complex numbers inside this square are not congruent to each other. Now draw adjacent squares, such as the squares whose vertices are 5+2i, 10+4i, 8+9i, 3+7i; or, 3+7i, 8+9i, 6+14i, 1+12i. All the numbers inside these squares are also not congruent to each other, but each number is congruent to the one number in each of the other squares, which is in the same relative position within the square. For example, 2+4i and 7+6i, occupy the same relative position within their respective squares, consequently, the difference (interval) between them is the modulus 5+2i.

Thus, the simple periodicity generated by congruences with respect to real numbers, is transformed into a double periodicity with respect to complex moduli. In a simply-extended manifold, therefore, subtraction determines the linear interval between two numbers, while in a doubly-extended manifold, subtraction determines the area interval between two numbers.

Gauss next developed a concept of doubly-extended “complex” multiplication, which will require you to re-think what you were taught about multiplying numbers in elementary school. Simply-extended multiplication was defined by Euclid as:

“15. A number is said to multiply a number when that which is multiplied is added to itself as many times as there are units in the other, and thus some number is produced.”

But, even Euclid admits an inadequacy of this concept in the next definition:

“16. And, when two numbers having multiplied one another make some number, the number so produced is called plane, and its sides are the numbers which have multiplied one another.”

But, we already have discovered from Theatetus, that adding in a simply-extended manifold, (lines) and adding in a doubly-extended manifold (areas) are not the same, so how can adding one number to itself “as many times as there are units in the other” (definition 15.) produce the areas described in definition 16? This darkness arises from the lack of a concept of multiply-extended magnitude.

The matter is resolved by a higher concept. If you look again at Theatetus’ alternating series of squares and rectangles, or the expanding series of squares from the Meno, you can see that adding areas produces a rotation and an extension. For example, the square whose area is 1 is transformed into the rectangle whose area is two, by rotating a line whose length is 1 90 degrees and multiplying its length by 2. The next transformation, to a square whose area is 4, is produced by the action of rotating the longer side of the rectangle and additional 90 degrees, and multiplying its length again by 2.

As Gauss’ follower Neils Henrick Abel said, “To know the truth, you must always invert.” An inversion, therefore, will show us the general principle that is, the action of adding rotation and multiplying lengths, produces the geometric progression.

So in the complex domain, multiplication is the action of adding rotations and multiplying lengths.

Illustrate this first with respect to prime numbers, by the example of multiplying (1+2i)(1-2i). 1+2i denotes a rotation of 45 degrees and a linear extension of ?5. 1-2i denotes a rotation of 45 degrees, in the opposite direction and a linear extension of ?5. To multiply the two magnitudes, add the rotations, (which together equal 0) and multiply the extensions (?5)(?5) = 5. Hence, 5, a prime number in a simply-extended manifold, is a composite number in a doubly- extended manifold. However, no such geometric action will produce odd-odd prime numbers such as 7, 11, 19, etc.

Gauss saw this paradox as an excellent pedagogical demonstration of the principle that the nature of the manifold determines nature of the magnitudes. Since prime numbers produce all numbers by multiplication, but cannot be produced themselves by multiplication, Gauss has shown that these magnitudes, (prime numbers) that produce other magnitudes (composite numbers) are themselves produced by the manifold in which the action (multiplication) takes place . Some numbers are prime (undeniable facts) but when a new principle (dimension) is added even those undeniable facts, are changed!

Now, construct a geometric progression from a complex number, by multiplying that number by itself repeatedly. For example, start with 1+i which denotes a rotation of 45 degrees and an extension of ?2. Then multiply 1+i times 1+i. This produces a rotation of 90 degrees and an extension of 2. Repeating this again produces a rotation of 135 degrees and an extension of 4. If you continue this action you will see unfolding points on a logarithmic spiral.

From this Gauss demonstrated that the periodicity produced by the residues of a geometric progression, actually reflected magnitudes of a higher manifold. In the next installment, we will illustrate this discovery.

Riemann for Anti-Dummies: Part 23: The Civil Rights of Complex Numbers

Riemann for Anti-Dummies Part 23

THE CIVIL RIGHTS OF COMPLEX NUMBERS

As the unfolding of current history demonstrates, it is reality that determines policy, not the other way around. This should come as no surprise to a scientific thinker knowledgeable in the method of Plato, Cusa, Kepler, Leibniz, Fermat, Gauss, Riemann and LaRouche. It is, however, shocking for anyone unfortunate enough to have accepted, wittingly or unwittingly, the delusion of Aristotle, Kant and Newton, that extensible magnitude exists outside the domain of universal physical principles.

This is the standpoint from which Gauss introduced his concept of the complex domain, beginning with his doctoral dissertation on the fundamental theorem of algebra, his Disquisitiones Arithmeticae, his treatises on geodesy and curvature, and his second treatise on biquadratic residues. From his earliest work, Gauss adopted the standpoint of his teacher Kaestner, and Leibniz before him, that the characteristic of extensible magnitude is a function of the manifold out of which those magnitudes were created.

It is in this light that one must view the discussions in the previous week’s installments. Gauss has rejected any {a priori} conception of magnitude, and instead derived the characteristic of numbers from a set of generating principles. First, by generating numbers from the juxtaposition of simple cycles, and then from the standpoint of a geometric cycle of cycles. As such, the relationships among numbers can not be found in the numbers themselves, but only in the relationship of those numbers to the manifold in which they exist. Like Leibniz’ monads, numbers don’t relate to each other directly, but only through the manifold from which they are created.

A quick review from last week illustrates the point. Take the “orbit” generated by the residues of the powers of the primitive root of 11 and 13.

Modulus 11:
Index: 0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5
Residue: {1,-10},{2,-9},{4,-7},{8,-3},{5,-6},{10,-1}
Index: 6, 7, 8, 9, 10
Residue: {9,-2}, {7,-4},{3,-8},{6,-5},{1,-10}
Modulus 13: 
Index: 0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6
Residue: {1,-12},{2,-11},{4,-9}, 8,-5}, {3,-10},{6,-7},{12,-1}
Index: 7, 8, 9, 10, 11, 12
Residue: {11,-2},{9,-4}, {5,-8},{10,-3},{7,-6}, {1,-12}

In both cases the orbit begins with 1 and ends with 1, ordering all the numbers between 1 and the modulus minus 1, according to a principle. That principle, at first does not appear obvious, but on further investigation, it reveals itself to be highly ordered. At the halfway point of the “orbit,” (the 5th power for 11 and the 6th power for 13), the residue is -1, which when squared equals 1.

In the case of 13, a further division by half is possible. This gets us to the 3rd power, whose residue is 8, which, when squared is congruent to -1 modulus 13. In other words, -1 is at half the orbit; the square root of -1 is at half of the half.

This phenomenon hints at a paradox that reveals the underlying geometry of the ordering principle that generates the numbers. In the above example we were “experimenting” with positive and negative whole numbers. Naive sense-certainty indicates that these numbers can be represented completely as equally spaced intervals along an infinitely extended straight line, with positive numbers lining up in one direction and the negative numbers in the other. However, under such a conception, the square root of -1 does not exist as a magnitude, yet, its existence was just discovered as the biquadratic root of 1, modulus 13. (8 = ?-1 mod 13; 82 = -1 mod 13; 84 = 1 mod 13.)

In other words, a species of magnitude exists, that can not be logically deduced from a manifold of one dimension. Euler concluded that such magnitudes were, therefore, “impossible.” Gauss, on the other hand, would not be restricted to a one-dimensional manifold, when an anomaly required an extension into two dimensions, in which such “impossible” magnitudes become “possible.” Not only were such magnitudes possible, but Gauss proclaimed, they deserved “complete civil rights.” As he stated in his announcement to the second treatise on biquadratic residues:

“It is this and nothing other, that for the true establishment of a theory of bi-quadratic residues, the field of higher arithmetic, that otherwise extends only to the real numbers, will be enlarged also to the imaginary, and these must be granted complete and equal civil rights, with the real. As soon as one considers this, these theories appear in an entirely new light, and the results attain a highly surprising simplicity.”

In a manifold of two dimensions, the relationship among objects is not restricted to the back and forth relationship of objects along a line, but also includes a relationship of up and down, so to speak. Be careful, this is not two separate relationships, back-forth and up-down. Rather it is one, doubly-extended relationship. As Gauss stated:

“Suppose, however, the objects are of such a nature that they can not be ordered in a single series, even if unbounded in both directions, but can only be ordered in a series of series, or in other words form a manifold of two dimensions….”

The root of this conception lies not in mathematics, but in physical geometry. In a fragmentary note, “On the Metaphysics of Mathematics,” Gauss described a doubly-extended relationship using the metaphor of a carpenter’s level. The bubble in the level can only move back and forth, if the ends of the level move up and down. Furthermore, Gauss repeatedly noted, such concepts as back and forth, up and down, left and right, can not be known, as Kant claimed, mathematically. Instead, such concepts are only known with respect to real physical objects.

This type of action is represented geometrically by two-dimensional magnitudes which Gauss called complex numbers. Gauss represented these numbers as the vertices of a grid of equally spaced squares on a plane. Be mindful. It is not the grid that generates the numbers. It is the {idea} of a doubly-extended manifold, that generates doubly-extended magnitudes, that form the grid. As in the case of the bubble in the carpenter’s level, any relationship between two complex numbers is a combination of horizontal and vertical action along the grid.

This geometrical representation of complex numbers flows easily from the geometry of the “orbits” generated by the residues of powers. For example, take the case of 13, (or any odd-even prime number modulus) as illustrated above. Think of the cycle of residues as a closed orbit, beginning with 1 and returning to 1. Halfway around the orbit is -1. One quarter the way around the orbit is the square root of -1. Three quarters around is minus the square root of -1.

This is the geometrical relationship that is reflected in the characteristics of the residues, and is nothing more than a generalization of the principle that Plato presents in the {Meno} and {Theatetus}, for the special case of squares. In that case, the diagonal of the square, which forms the side of a square whose area is double the original square, is called the geometric mean. The diagonal has the same relationship to the two squares, as -1 does to 1, and the square root of -1 does to -1.

Gauss described the manifold of complex numbers this way:

“We must add some general remarks. To locate the theory of biquadratic residues in the domain of the complex numbers might seem objectionable and unnatural to those unfamiliar with the nature of imaginary numbers and caught in false conceptions of the same; such people might be led to the opinion that our investigations are built on mere air, become doubtful, and distance themselves from our views. Nothing could be so groundless as such an opinion. Quite the opposite, the arithmetic of the complex numbers is most perfectly capable of visual representation, even though the author, in his presentation has followed a purely arithmetic treatment; nevertheless he has provided sufficient indications for the independently thinking reader to elaborate such a representation, which enlivens the insight and is therefore highly to be recommended.

“Just as the absolute whole numbers can be represented as a series of equally spaced points on a line, in which the initial point stands for 0, the next in line for 1, and so forth; and just as the representation of the negative whole numbers requires only an unlimited extension of that series on the opposite side of the initial point; so we require for a representation of the complex whole numbers only one addition: namely, that the said series should be thought of as lying in an unbounded plane, and parallel with it on both sides an unlimited number of similar series spaced at equal intervals from each other should be imagined, so that we have before us a system of points rather than only a series, a system which can be ordered in two ways as series of series and which serves to divide the entire plane into identical squares.

“The neighboring point to 0 in the first row to the one side of the original series corresponds to the number {i,} and the neighboring point to 0 on the other side to -i and so forth. Using this mapping, it becomes possible to represent in visual terms the arithmetic operations on complex magnitudes, congruences, construction of a complete system of incongruent numbers for a given modulus, and so forth, in a completely satisfactory manner.

“In this way, also, the true metaphysics of the imaginary magnitudes is shown in a new, clear light….”

Consequently, the domain of whole numbers has been extended beyond simply positive and negative numbers, to numbers of the form “a+bi“, where “i” stands for the square root of -1. These numbers are represented as points on a plane, in which “a” expresses the horizontal action while “b” the vertical action. For example, 2+3i would be represented by a point 2 to the right of 0 and 3 up from 2; 5+4i would be represented by 5 to the right of 0 and 4 up from 5. The difference (interval) between 2+3i and 5+4i would be 3+i, which is the combined amount of horizontal and vertical action required to move from 2+3i to 5+4i.

In Gauss’ complex domain, the fundamental characteristics of numbers are re-defined. Of particular importance is prime numbers. Here, numbers that are prime in a simply-extended manifold, are no longer prime in the complex domain. For example, 5, can be factored into the complex numbers (1+2i)(1-2i); or 13 into (3+2i)(3-2i). Gauss showed that all odd-even prime numbers are no longer prime in the complex domain, while all odd-odd prime numbers are still prime. Gauss went on to discover a new type of prime number that he called complex primes, which are now called “Gaussian primes.” These are complex numbers of the form a+bi, where a2 + b 2 is a prime number. (The geometrical demonstration of this principle will be developed in a subsequent installment.)

Thus, prime numbers, the “stuff” from which all numbers are made, are themselves not primary. Instead, they are defined by the nature of the manifold in which they exist. A one-dimensional manifold produces a certain set of prime numbers, whose “primeness” is absolute within a one-dimensional manifold, but relative with respect to a two-dimensional manifold. In turn, a two-dimensional manifold produces prime numbers whose characteristic “primeness” is different from what constitutes “primeness” in a one-dimensional manifold. The characteristic “primeness” of one-dimensional prime numbers can be derived from the characteristic of “primeness” of two dimensions, but not vice versa. Implicit in this, is a hierarchy of dimensionality, in which the singularities of n-dimensions are subsumed and transformed by manifolds of higher dimensions. Gauss himself anticipated such an idea stating:

“The author reserves the possibility of treating these matters, only barely touched upon in this paper, more fully at a later date, at which time we shall also answer the question, why such relations between things as form manifolds of more than two dimensions might not provide additional species of magnitudes to be admitted in general Arithmetic.”

This is only a taste of the manifold of ideas manifest in the minds of the hearers of Riemann’s habilitation lecture. The more this manifold begins to order your mind’s thoughts, the more lively Riemann’s ideas will become.

Riemann for Anti-Dummies: Part 22: Your Education was Not Merely Incompetent

Your Education Was Not Merely Incompetent

If you felt a little disconcerted to sit in the same lecture hall with C.F. Gauss, listening to B. Riemann deliver his habilitation address, do not despair. Be happy. You are being afforded the opportunity to discover that your education was not merely incompetent, it was also malicious. Incompetent, in that your teachers were most likely totally ignorant of the most significant original discoveries upon which the human race has depended for survival; malicious, in that the system to which the teachers acquiesced, had no intention of producing individuals capable of making such discoveries. As we now see from the events unfolding around us, a system which does not intend to produce creative individuals, has no intention of surviving. Therefore, rejoice at the occasion to clear your head of the restrictive fixation on facts, laws, opinions, and popularly held beliefs, and set about the task of producing creative thinkers.

Riemann sought to “lift the darkness” that had settled on science for more than 2000 years, by providing for science a general concept of multiply-extended magnitude. A concept in which it was recognized, that magnitude had no {a priori} characteristics, but was itself determined by the nature of the manifold in which it existed which nature was only determined by experiment. Riemann’s taking off point was Gauss’ work on physical geometry and arithmetic, which was itself the revolutionary result of Gauss’ early education in the work of Kepler, Leibniz, Bach, Kaestner, and the scientific achievements of classical Greece. Central to all these discoveries was the desire to discover the principles that generated the objects of investigation, be it physical objects, such as the motions of the planets, living processes, or objects of cognition, the latter being the most fundamental, upon which all other investigations depend.

In this regard, Plato recognized that the mind must be trained to investigate itself, to which end he prescribed the study of geometry, astronomy, music and arithmetic, the latter, because, “thought begins to be aroused within us, and the soul perplexed and wanting to arrive at a decision asks `Where is absolute unity?’ This is the way in which the study of the One has a power of drawing and converting the mind to the contemplation of true being … and, because this will be the easiest way for the soul herself to pass from becoming to truth and being….”

That search for the nature of unity underlies Gauss’ arithmetical investigations. Its revolutionary feature being that the nature of unity, is itself not a fixed, but developing and changing. This is what underlies Gauss’ concept of congruence, the ordering of numbers with respect to a modulus. This is based on the principle that numbers are not fixed objects that determine order, but are themselves ordered, according to the principle from which they are generated.

The first principle is the generation of numbers from the juxtaposition of cycles. These juxtapositions form two types of relationships. Either the cycles equally divide one another, such as a cycle of 8 and a cycle of 4, or no such division is generated, such as a cycle of 5 and a cycle of 8. In the latter case, that relationship is called, “relatively prime”. Those cycles, which when juxtaposed to all smaller cycles and One were called simply “prime”, and until Gauss were thought of as absolutely prime, or prime relative to One.

Thus when thinking about numbers from the bottom up, as formed by adding 1 to 1 to 1, the prime numbers are mysterious and arise from an unknown. However, when thought about from the top down, the prime numbers are that from which all numbers are made. The question that Gauss and Riemann contemplated was, “what principle generates prime numbers”. This led to the investigation, not of the numbers, but of the manifolds in which those numbers were generated.

The investigation of those manifolds leads to the second principle of generation. This is the principle which the Greeks called “geometric”, and was examined in last week’s installment. This is where today’s work begins.

Take the example from last week — the investigation of the cycle of residues generated with respect to modulus 11 and compare that to the cycle of residues with respect to modulus 13. For the sake of brevity, I indicate only the cycle with respect to one primitive root. The first row is the index, or power to which the primitive root is raised, and the second row is the corresponding residue. For reasons that will become apparent, we include both the positive and negative residues:

Modulus 11:
     Index:  0,      1,     2,     3,     4,     5 
   Residue: {1,-10},{2,-9},{4,-7},{8,-3},{5,-6},{10,-1}
     Index:  6,      7,     8,     9,    10 
   Residue: {9,-2}, {7,-4},{3,-8},{6,-5},{1,-10}
Modulus 13: 
     Index:  0,      1,     2,      3,      4,      5,    6 
   Residue: {1,-12},{2,-11},{4,-9}, 8,-5}, {3,-10},{6,-7},{12,-1} 
     Index:  7,      8,     9,      10,     11,     12 
   Residue: {11,-2},{9,-4}, {5,-8},{10,-3},{7,-6}, {1,-12}

In both cases, half the residues, that is, the residues of even powers, are residues of squares, (quadratic residues). The residues of the other half, the residues of odd powers, are residues of rectangles (quadratic non-residues). In the case of 13, the quadratic residues are the same whether negative or positive. While with 11, the positive quadratic residues are different than the non-residues.

This indicates an at first surprising connection between the ancient Pythagorean discovery of odd and even, which seems to pertain to numbers, and the geometric progression, which seems to pertain to figures in space. That odd and even reflected a deeper principle was described by Cusa in “On Conjectures”:

“It is established that every number is constituted out of unity and otherness, the unity advancing to otherness and otherness regressing to unity, so that it is limited in this reciprocal progression and subsists in actuality as it is. It can also not be that the unity of one number is completely equal to the unity of another, since a precise equality is impossible in everything finite. Unity and otherness are therefore varied in every number. The odd number appears to have more of unity than the even number, because the former cannot be divided into equal parts and the latter can be. Therefore, since every number is one out of unity and otherness, so there will be numbers in which the unity prevails over the otherness, and others in which the otherness appears to absorb the unity.”

It doesn’t stop with the division into even and odd, as both types have a deeper nature. The even numbers can be divided, into those even numbers, such as 10, that, when divided form two odd numbers (5 and 5), and those, such as 12, that form two even numbers (6 and 6). The former are called even-odd, the latter even-even. Likewise odd numbers can be divided into two types. Odd numbers, like 11, that are one more than an even-odd number and are called odd-odd, while odd numbers, like 13, that are one more than an even-even and are called odd-even. (Gauss called odd-even numbers 4n+1, and odd-odd numbers 4n+3.)

Now look at the mid-point of each of the above “orbits” of residues. As we showed at the end of last week’s installment, the midpoint of the orbit is both the arithmetic and the geometric mean. The arithmetic, because it is half the length of the cycle. The geometric, because its half the rotation from the 1 to 1, or the square root of 1. For modulus 11, that residue is either 10 or -1, both of which, when squared, are congruent to 1 modulus 11. For modulus 13, that residue is either 12 or -1, both of which, when squared, are congruent to 1 modulus 13.

Illustrate this in your mind, using Plato’s alternating series of squares and rectangles. In a cycle of 10 squares and rectangles, the 5th action is a rectangle, whose area is 32. That area is the geometric mean between a square whose area is 1 and the square whose area is 1024. Since the residues form a cycle that begins and ends with 1, the residue of the 5th power, mod 11, is the geometric mean between 1 and 1. Similarly, with a cycle of 12 squares and rectangles, the 6th action produces a square whose area is 64. That square is the geometric mean between a square whose area is 1 and a square whose area is 4096. With respect to modulus 11, the geometric mean is a rectangle, while for modulus 13, the geometric mean is a square.

But, there’s a difference between modulus 11 and modulus 13, as 11 is odd-odd, which means the half-way point is an odd number, that is 5. While 13 is odd-even, and is susceptible of further division, into quarters.

The residue of the 1/4 power relative to modulus 13 is either 8 or -5, both of which when squared twice, are congruent to 1 modulus 13. But, when both are squared once, they are congruent to -1 modulus 13. In other words, 8 and 5, -8 and -5, are congruent to the square root of minus 1 modulus 13.

Thus, the square root of -1 has clearly defined existence with respect to an odd-even modulus, while it has no existence in a manifold generated with respect to an odd-odd modulus.

From the naive standpoint, it would appear that the square root of -1 is a product of characteristic of oddness. But, as Cusa states, oddness is a quality in which unity prevails over otherness. So, rather than look for the square root of -1 in nature of oddness, look for the nature of oddness in the characteristic of unity.

This is precisely the way Gauss approached the problem. Rather than think of a manifold of a simply extended unity, he conceived of a manifold of a doubly extended unity, in which the square root of -1 is a “natural product” so to speak. He called this manifold the complex domain.

In his words:

“From this, we had already begun to ponder these objects in 1805, and we soon came to the conviction that the natural source of a general theory be sought in an extension of the field of Arithmetic.

“While higher arithmetic, has until now dealt only with questions pertaining to whole numbers, propositions concerning biquadratic residues appear in their complete simplicity and natural beauty, only if the field of arithmetic is extended to include imaginary numbers, without limitation, the numbers of the form a+bi forms its object, where the customary i denotes the square root of -1 and a and b are all whole numbers between minus infinity and plus infinity.”

Next week we’ll put flesh and bones on this new concept.

Riemann for Anti-Dummies: Part 21 : It is Principles, Not Numbers that Count

It is Principles, Not Numbers, That Count

As we continue the investigations into the “hints” from Gauss, to which Riemann referred in his 1854 habilitation lecture, it is vitally important to maintain the perspective of a member of the audience in the lecture hall that June day when Riemann delivered his revolutionary address. Don’t be a fearful, passive observer. Go in. Take the open seat next to the 77 year old Gauss and hear these living ideas, not only as they were spoken then, but as they are today, alive and transformed in the mind and work of LaRouche, for which Riemann provides brief hints.

Listen as Riemann boldly proposes “to lift the darkness” that has existed for more than 2000 years, by elaborating a “general concept of multiply-extended magnitude”. But, before you can even begin to lift that darkness, you must first realize that the lights aren’t on.

That is the basis on which the preliminary exercises into the investigations of the geometry of numbers was begun last week.

Gauss is training the mind to give up all deductive, a priori, notions of number. Instead of investigating numbers, we investigate what generates them. It is the principle of generation to which we must turn our thoughts, aided by concepts from Classical art. The numbers are simply players, guides to what’s in between.

The first principle of generation of numbers, to which Gauss points, is the generation of numbers by the juxtaposition of three cycles. While this concept was introduced in a new form in the Disquisitiones Arithmeticae, by the concept of congruence with respect to a modulus, the principle underlying it is perhaps the earliest, and most elementary concept of number. In this case, no number exists on its own. Rather, all numbers exist as players, whose parts are a function of their relationship to one another and a One, which Gauss called a modulus. Thus, all numbers are ordered according to the characteristics of the modulus. Those characteristics are themselves determined by an underlying generating principle, which will become more clear below. The so-called, “natural”, counting numbers are only the special case, of numbers ordered with respect to the modulus 1.

The second principle of generation to which Gauss turned his attention, is generating numbers from a cycle of cycles, specifically, the “geometric” cycle. Here each cycle is generated by the function described by Plato in the Theatetus dialogue, as reflected in the alternating series of squares and rectangles produced by some repeated action, such as doubling or tripling, etc. However, Gauss, as Plato, Kepler, Leibniz, Bernoulli and Fermat before him, understood that the alternating series of squares and rectangles, was itself only a shadow of a higher principle of generation, that had to be discovered.

Naive sense certainty says this geometric progression is not a cycle at all, but open ended and continuously growing. Yet, as the experiments at the end of last week’s installment illustrate, if each “stage” of the geometric progression is thought of as a cycle, and each such cycle is juxtaposed to a third cycle (modulus), an underlying periodicity is revealed, indicating the characteristics of the cycle that generated each stage.

The principle of generation of that underlying cycle, is best investigated by experiment. Hopefully, you carried out the experiment indicated last week. If so, you will have no trouble producing the necessary geometric constructions.

Construct a chart of the residues of powers with respect to modulus 11 by first making a row of numbers from 0 to 10. These denote the powers. Then make a separate row of the residues of the powers of 2 through 10, writing each residue under the corresponding power. The result should be the following:

Powers: 0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9,10 
     2: 1, 2, 4, 8. 5, 10,9, 7, 3, 6, 1 
     3: 1, 3, 9, 3, 4, 1, 3, 9, 5, 4, 1 
     4: 1, 4, 5, 9, 3, 1, 4, 5, 9, 3, 1 
     5: 1, 5, 3, 4, 9, 1, 5, 3, 4, 9, 1 
     6: 1, 6, 3, 7, 9, 10,5, 8, 4, 2, 1 
     7: 1, 7, 5, 2, 3, 10,4, 6, 9, 8, 1 
     8: 1, 8, 9, 6, 4, 10,3, 2, 5, 7, 1 
     9: 1, 9, 4, 3, 5, 1, 9, 4, 3, 5, 1 
    10: 1,10, 1, 10,1, 10,1, 10,1,10, 1

Now have some fun. Obviously, this action produces, from the open and growing geometric cycle, a regular structured periodicity. The question Fermat, Leibniz, and Gauss investigated was, “What generating principle produces this?” To begin to answer this, they looked for the paradoxes, within the seemingly regular structure.

First, it is clear that each period begins and ends with 1 and there are three types of periods. Those periods, such as for the powers of 2, 6, 7, and 8, that are 10 numbers long and include all the numbers between 1 and 10. Gauss called these numbers, 2,6,7 and 8 “primitive roots” of 11. The second type of period, for the powers of 3, 4, 5, and 9 are 5 numbers long. The third type of period is the powers of 10 which is only 2 numbers long. Thus, the residues of powers with respect to modulus 11 permits only certain size “orbits” so to speak, which are restricted to the size of 10 and the prime number factors of 10, that is, 2 and 5.

Now, even though each period puts the numbers in a different order, this order is highly determined. To see this, hunt through the whole chart and circle the primitive roots, 2, 6, 7, and 8, wherever they appear. You should discover that these numbers do not appear as residues, except in the periods that are 10 numbers long. Also, even though they appear in different places in each period, they always are residues of the powers 1, 3, 7, or 9, which are the numbers that are relatively prime to 10.

This begins to reveal the nature of the underlying generating principle of these “orbits”, as the characteristics of the number 10, specifically its prime factors and its relative primes, determine the ordering of the periods!

Keeping this in your mind’s eye, draw an alternating series of squares and rectangles, first by doubling, then by tripling, and label each according to the residue from the powers of 2 and 3 respectively to which it corresponds. This will reveal that the even powers correspond to squares and the odd powers correspond to rectangles. Notice how the residue 1 only appears on a square and the residue 10 only appears on a rectangle. Also, the squares always correspond to even numbered powers, while the rectangles correspond to odd numbered powers.

Thus, the quality of odd and even, reflect a geometric characteristic, not a numerical property of numbers. For these geometrical reasons, Gauss called the residues of the even powers, “quadratic residues” and the residues of the odd powers, “quadratic non-residues”. Gauss paid special attention to this characteristic, for its investigation opened the door to some of the most profound principles. In the next installment we will explore this more fully.

But, before closing, look at one more anomaly. Notice that the residue at the halfway point, that is the residue of the power 5, is always 1 or 10. Since 10 is congruent to -1, the residue of the middle power is always 1 or -1. While 5 is the arithmetic mean between 0 and 10, its residue, 1 or -1 is the geometric mean between 1 and 1! In other words, 1 and 10 are the square roots of 1 relative to modulus 11.

Look back over the preceding investigations from the perspective of a classical drama. Think of the foregoing as a drama of 10 characters. Each character has several roles, in which they wear the same costume, but do different things. The playwright has deliberately chosen this device so that the audience can be broken from judging these characters by naive sense-certainty. This helps convey an idea that could not be expressed in words by any of the characters, but only by the totality of all their actions taken as a whole, and the ironies revealed when the same actor does something completely different, without changing his costume. Each number from 1 to 10 has a different function, whether it’s a power, a residue, or a base. In some roles, the obvious characteristics of the number, such as odd or even, factor or relative prime, seem to affect its function, but in other cases, such as the primitive roots, these obvious characteristics seem to have no bearing. Only when all the roles are played out can we begin to taste the intention of the playwright.

Gauss could see that these anomalies could not be derived from a concept of number, in the naive sense of an object that counts things, but, rather, these anomalies revealed an underlying {geometric} generating principle, that shone through the numbers themselves. But, to bring out that light, required a complete revolution in the way people thought about number. As he said in the beginning of the first Treatise on Bi-quadratic Residues, “we soon came to the knowledge, that the customary principles of arithmetic, are in no way sufficient for the foundation of a general theory, and that it is very much necessary, that the region of higher arithmetic be, so to speak, infinitely much more extended.”

Riemann for Anti-Dummies: Part 20 : Gauss’ Attack on Deductive Thinking

Gauss’ Attack on Deductive Thinking

In his 1854 habilitation dissertation, Bernhard Riemann referred to two “hints” as preliminary to his development of an anti-Euclidean geometry–specifically Gauss’ second treatise on bi-quadratic residues and Gauss’ essay on the theory of curved surfaces. It is but one more testament to the ignorance of all so-called experts today, (not to mention those who wish to qualify as educated citizens) that direct knowledge of these two works by Gauss, let alone a working understanding of Riemann himself, is virtually non-existent.

It should not be surprising that in a lecture focused on ridding science of “ivory tower” mathematics, Riemann would refer to the climactic conclusion of Gauss’ investigation of whole numbers. Riemann, like Gauss and Leibniz before him, began his scientific education by confronting the paradoxes that emerge from an anti-deductive investigation of whole numbers. At an early age, Riemann was given a copy of Legendre’s “Theory of Numbers”, and within one week he returned the 600 page book saying, “This is wonderful book. I know it by heart.”

Plato prescribed such investigations as necessary for the development of competent leadership, because it forced the mind out of realm of sense-certainty and into the realm of paradoxes where, “thought begins to be aroused within us, and the soul perplexed and wanting to arrive at a decision asks `Where is absolute unity?’ This is the way in which the study of the One has a power of drawing and converting the mind to the contemplation of true being.,,,we must endeavor to persuade those who are to be the principal men of our State to go and learn arithmetic, not as amateurs, but they must carry on the study {until they see the nature of numbers with the mind only;} nor again, like merchants or retail-traders, with a view to buying or selling, but for the sake of their military use, and of the soul herself; and because this will be the easiest way for her to pass from becoming to truth and being….”

And as LaRouche pointed out in “Marat, DeSade & Greenspin”:

“Since the beginning of the Nineteenth Century, Carl Gauss’s {Disquisitiones Arithmeticae}, inspired by his teacher, the great founder of anti-Euclidean geometry, Abraham K„stner, had been the standard for competent mathematics instruction. This masterpiece should be the recognized standard, even today, for basic secondary and higher education in mathematics. The result of replacing that standard with “the new math” program, should have reminded any literate professional of Jonathan Swift’s famous description of education as practiced on the allegorical floating island of Laputa.”

To ameliorate this pitiable condition of mankind, and save any readers of these pedagogicals from being condemned to perpetual flatulence on Laputa, the next installments of this series will begin to acquaint the reader with the basic conceptions of these two works by Gauss, as a prerequisite to looking more deeply into Riemann’s work itself.

To begin, you must, as Gauss does, give up all deductive notions of number. Instead of thinking of whole numbers as self-evident things in themselves, think of numbers as being generated by a principle. Gauss took an experimental approach to numbers, designing experiments that revealed paradoxes with respect to a known principle. The resolution of that paradox required the introduction of a new principle. Gauss himself described the approach to be taken in our investigations:

“The questions of higher arithmetic often present a remarkable characteristic which seldom appears in more general analysis, and increases the beauty of the former subject. While analytic investigations lead to the discovery of new truths only after the fundamental principles of the subject (which to a certain degree open the way to these truths) have been completely mastered; on the contrary in arithmetic the most elegant theorems frequently arise experimentally as the result of a more or less unexpected stroke of good fortune, while their proofs lie so deeply embedded in the darkness that they elude all attempts and defeat the sharpest inquiries…. These truths are frequently of such a nature that they may be arrived at by many distinct paths and that the first paths to be discovered are not always the shortest. It is therefore a great pleasure after one has fruitlessly pondered over a truth and has later been able to prove it in a round-about way to find at last the simplest and most natural way to its proof.”

The opening motivic idea of the Disquisitiones, is to identify numbers as being generated by an interval, or modulus, much the same way as musical notes are generated by intervals. If the interval between two numbers is divisible by the modulus, Gauss called those numbers, “congruent”. For example, 2, 7, 12, 17, 22, etc, are all congruent to each other relative to modulus 5. Relative to modulus 7, 2 is congruent to 9, 16, 23,etc.

Gauss’ use of the term congruence is consistent with Kepler’s use of that concept in Book II of his “Harmonies of the World”. For Kepler the word “congruentia” was the Latin equivalent to the Greek word, “harmonia”, which means to fit together. Thus, it is not the numbers on which the mind must focus, but the way they fit together.

Gauss’ concept of congruence reflects the actual nature of numbers more truthfully than the so-called “natural” ordering of numbers that seemed so commonsensical when you learned it in school. This is because, contrary to such common sense certainty notions, the concept of number does not arise from counting things. Rather, it arises from the juxtaposition of cycles, such as, for example, astronomical cycles. Each cycle is a One, but when juxtaposed to each other these cycles give rise to a multiplicity.

As Leibniz puts it in his doctoral dissertation, “On the Art of Combinations”:

“Furthermore, every relation is either one of union or one of harmony. In union the things between which there is this relation are called parts, and taken together with their union, is a whole. This happens whenever we take many things simultaneously as one. By one we mean whatever we think of in one intellectual act, or at once. For example, we often grasp a number, however large, all at once in a kind of blind thought, namely, when we read figures on paper which not even the age of Methuselah would suffice to count explicitly.

“The concept of unity is abstracted from the concept of one being, and the whole itself, abstracted from unities, or the totality, is called number.”

Any two cycles can be known in relation to each other only by a third. For example, the cycle discovered by the Greek astronomer Meton who attempted to resolve the lunar month and solar year cycles into a One. One solar cycle contains 12 lunar cycles, plus a small residue, so in Gauss’ words, the lunar cycle is {incongruent} with the solar one. However, Meton discovered that 19 solar years contains 235 lunar months with no residue. So, while one lunar month is not congruent to one solar year, one lunar month is congruent to 19 solar years. The relationship between the solar cycle and lunar cycle can be known with respect to this 19 year Metonic cycle, which defines the modulus under which the solar and lunar cycles are congruent.

To get familiar with this concept play with some more examples. Consider two cycles one of which is three times longer than the other. These cycles would be congruent to each other relative to modulus three. Examples of this relationship expressed in numbers would include: 3 is congruent to 9 relative to modulus 3, or 9 is congruent to 27 relative to modulus 3.

Now consider cycles that don’t fit exactly, such as a cycle of 4 and a cycle of 9. The smaller cycle of 4 will fit into the larger cycle of 9 twice with a residue of 1. Under Gauss’ concept, 9 is congruent to 1 relative to modulus 4. On the other hand, a cycle of 4 fits into a cycle of 10 twice with a residue of 2. Under Gauss’ concept, 10 is congruent to 2 relative to modulus 4. Continuing, a cycle of 4 fits into a cycle of 11 with a residue of 3. Thus, 11 is congruent to 3 relative to modulus 4. Further, a cycle of 4 fits into a cycle of 12 with 0 residue, and into a cycle of 13 with a residue of 1. Thus, a cycle of 4 will fit into any cycle with a residue of 0, 1, 2, or 3.

If you play around with this idea, trying cycles of different relationships, you will discover for yourself, that any modulus defines a period, from 0 to the modulus minus 1. This will probably strain your brain, as you will be forcing yourself to think in terms of relationships instead of things, but that is precisely why all great thinkers, from Plato onward, struggled to free themselves from the straight jacket of deductive relationships by investigating the nature of numbers.

This would probably be enough to get you started, but in order to speed up our pursuit of the concepts in Gauss’ second treatise of bi-quadratic residues, we should push ahead.

After developing the concept of congruence in the beginning of the Disquistiones, Gauss turns to an investigation of what he called, “residues of powers”. Here you must leave completely the world of sense certainty and deductive reasoning.

By “powers” Gauss meant the concept developed by Plato in the Theatetus dialogue. These are the magnitudes associated with action in what Riemann would call a doubly extended manifold. Shadows of these magnitudes are represented by Plato as the successive doublings, triplings, etc. of squares. When these magnitudes are expressed in whole numbers it generates a geometric series such as: 1, 2, 4, 8, 16, 32, 64, 128, 256, 512, etc. or: 1, 3, 9, 27, 81, 243, 729, 2187, 6561, etc.

If you think of each number as a cycle, the series can be thought of as a cycle of cycles. This cycle of cycles doesn’t close, but gets bigger and bigger, according to a self-similar proportionality.

What may appear shocking to you, is that this open, growing, cycle of cycles generates a periodic, closed, cycle with respect to a modulus.

For example, take the geometric series formed from doubling squares and find the residues relative to modulus 3. This yields the period: 1, 2, 1, 2, 1, 2, 1, 2, etc. Now do the same for modulus 5. This yields the period: 1, 2, 4, 3, 1, 2, 4, 3, 1, 2, 4, 3, 1, etc. And for 7: 1, 2, 4, 1, 2, 4, 1, 2, 4, 1,etc. Try the same experiment with respect to the geometric series based on tripling. For modulus 5 it yields the period: 1, 3, 4, 2, 1, 3, 4, 2, 1, etc. Compare this with the period generated from the same modulus but the geometric series based on doubling. Modulus 7 for the same series yields the period: 1, 3, 2, 6, 4, 5, 1, 3, 2, 6, 4, 5, 1,etc.

This experiment is a simple example of what Gauss described as discovering certain truths by experiment. From where does this periodicity arise? What is its nature? What principles does it reflect?

Experiment with other geometric series and other moduli. Next week we will plunge ahead.